Explain Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory in layman terms












6














What does Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory mean?



According to Wikipedia, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory is a set theory that is proposed to overcome issues in naive set theory. I really appreciate if somebody can kindly explain the basic concepts involved in this Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory so that high school students can understand.










share|cite|improve this question




















  • 7




    Math.StackExchange is not an encyclopedia, and questions should be narrower than "explain X so that I can understand it". Do you have any particular questions about the Wikipedia article?
    – Trevor Wilson
    Feb 21 '13 at 3:54






  • 3




    Roughly speaking, the contradictions in naive set theory seemed to come from its use of very broad, and imprecise, set construction principles. ZF attempts to pin down precise and fairly narrow set construction principles, enough for most of mathematics, but not so generous (one hopes) as to lead to contradictions.
    – André Nicolas
    Feb 21 '13 at 3:56












  • I will be more than happy to add on my answer below, but you will have to tell me if anything is unclear.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Feb 21 '13 at 11:18










  • If you are trying to introduce formal proof to advanced high school students, the ZF axioms may not be the best starting point. I have developed a simplified version of set theory and first order logic as the basis for my educational freeware that may be more appropriate. Visit my website at dcproof.com for video demo and free, full-function download.
    – Dan Christensen
    May 7 '15 at 15:05


















6














What does Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory mean?



According to Wikipedia, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory is a set theory that is proposed to overcome issues in naive set theory. I really appreciate if somebody can kindly explain the basic concepts involved in this Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory so that high school students can understand.










share|cite|improve this question




















  • 7




    Math.StackExchange is not an encyclopedia, and questions should be narrower than "explain X so that I can understand it". Do you have any particular questions about the Wikipedia article?
    – Trevor Wilson
    Feb 21 '13 at 3:54






  • 3




    Roughly speaking, the contradictions in naive set theory seemed to come from its use of very broad, and imprecise, set construction principles. ZF attempts to pin down precise and fairly narrow set construction principles, enough for most of mathematics, but not so generous (one hopes) as to lead to contradictions.
    – André Nicolas
    Feb 21 '13 at 3:56












  • I will be more than happy to add on my answer below, but you will have to tell me if anything is unclear.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Feb 21 '13 at 11:18










  • If you are trying to introduce formal proof to advanced high school students, the ZF axioms may not be the best starting point. I have developed a simplified version of set theory and first order logic as the basis for my educational freeware that may be more appropriate. Visit my website at dcproof.com for video demo and free, full-function download.
    – Dan Christensen
    May 7 '15 at 15:05
















6












6








6


5





What does Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory mean?



According to Wikipedia, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory is a set theory that is proposed to overcome issues in naive set theory. I really appreciate if somebody can kindly explain the basic concepts involved in this Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory so that high school students can understand.










share|cite|improve this question















What does Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory mean?



According to Wikipedia, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory is a set theory that is proposed to overcome issues in naive set theory. I really appreciate if somebody can kindly explain the basic concepts involved in this Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory so that high school students can understand.







soft-question set-theory intuition axioms






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Feb 21 '13 at 4:09









MJD

46.9k28208392




46.9k28208392










asked Feb 21 '13 at 3:48









isharp

442




442








  • 7




    Math.StackExchange is not an encyclopedia, and questions should be narrower than "explain X so that I can understand it". Do you have any particular questions about the Wikipedia article?
    – Trevor Wilson
    Feb 21 '13 at 3:54






  • 3




    Roughly speaking, the contradictions in naive set theory seemed to come from its use of very broad, and imprecise, set construction principles. ZF attempts to pin down precise and fairly narrow set construction principles, enough for most of mathematics, but not so generous (one hopes) as to lead to contradictions.
    – André Nicolas
    Feb 21 '13 at 3:56












  • I will be more than happy to add on my answer below, but you will have to tell me if anything is unclear.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Feb 21 '13 at 11:18










  • If you are trying to introduce formal proof to advanced high school students, the ZF axioms may not be the best starting point. I have developed a simplified version of set theory and first order logic as the basis for my educational freeware that may be more appropriate. Visit my website at dcproof.com for video demo and free, full-function download.
    – Dan Christensen
    May 7 '15 at 15:05
















  • 7




    Math.StackExchange is not an encyclopedia, and questions should be narrower than "explain X so that I can understand it". Do you have any particular questions about the Wikipedia article?
    – Trevor Wilson
    Feb 21 '13 at 3:54






  • 3




    Roughly speaking, the contradictions in naive set theory seemed to come from its use of very broad, and imprecise, set construction principles. ZF attempts to pin down precise and fairly narrow set construction principles, enough for most of mathematics, but not so generous (one hopes) as to lead to contradictions.
    – André Nicolas
    Feb 21 '13 at 3:56












  • I will be more than happy to add on my answer below, but you will have to tell me if anything is unclear.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Feb 21 '13 at 11:18










  • If you are trying to introduce formal proof to advanced high school students, the ZF axioms may not be the best starting point. I have developed a simplified version of set theory and first order logic as the basis for my educational freeware that may be more appropriate. Visit my website at dcproof.com for video demo and free, full-function download.
    – Dan Christensen
    May 7 '15 at 15:05










7




7




Math.StackExchange is not an encyclopedia, and questions should be narrower than "explain X so that I can understand it". Do you have any particular questions about the Wikipedia article?
– Trevor Wilson
Feb 21 '13 at 3:54




Math.StackExchange is not an encyclopedia, and questions should be narrower than "explain X so that I can understand it". Do you have any particular questions about the Wikipedia article?
– Trevor Wilson
Feb 21 '13 at 3:54




3




3




Roughly speaking, the contradictions in naive set theory seemed to come from its use of very broad, and imprecise, set construction principles. ZF attempts to pin down precise and fairly narrow set construction principles, enough for most of mathematics, but not so generous (one hopes) as to lead to contradictions.
– André Nicolas
Feb 21 '13 at 3:56






Roughly speaking, the contradictions in naive set theory seemed to come from its use of very broad, and imprecise, set construction principles. ZF attempts to pin down precise and fairly narrow set construction principles, enough for most of mathematics, but not so generous (one hopes) as to lead to contradictions.
– André Nicolas
Feb 21 '13 at 3:56














I will be more than happy to add on my answer below, but you will have to tell me if anything is unclear.
– Asaf Karagila
Feb 21 '13 at 11:18




I will be more than happy to add on my answer below, but you will have to tell me if anything is unclear.
– Asaf Karagila
Feb 21 '13 at 11:18












If you are trying to introduce formal proof to advanced high school students, the ZF axioms may not be the best starting point. I have developed a simplified version of set theory and first order logic as the basis for my educational freeware that may be more appropriate. Visit my website at dcproof.com for video demo and free, full-function download.
– Dan Christensen
May 7 '15 at 15:05






If you are trying to introduce formal proof to advanced high school students, the ZF axioms may not be the best starting point. I have developed a simplified version of set theory and first order logic as the basis for my educational freeware that may be more appropriate. Visit my website at dcproof.com for video demo and free, full-function download.
– Dan Christensen
May 7 '15 at 15:05












2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes


















19














In mathematics we have an idea, some concept. For example the idea of "set" was modeled after the idea that two collections are equal if they have the same members.



If I list your family it doesn't matter if I'm listing your father before you mother, or vice versa. I am only interested in the members. Similarly if I listed exactly the members of your family then this is a list of your family.



So sets were models after this idea. But we want more from sets, we want them to have certain properties. And at first we assumed these properties must always hold, but it turned out that there is an inherent contradiction in naive set theory.



So mathematicians of the early $20^{text{th}}$ century suggested axioms, which are strict rules that the mathematical objects called "sets" must obey. Amongst those mathematicians there were Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, after which the theory is named.



Before we start, let me just add one definition. Given two sets, $A$ and $B$ we say that $A$ is a subset of $B$ if all the members of $A$ are members of $B$. For example, all the students in your class are also students in your high school, so the set of your classmates if a subset of the set of your schoolmates.



The axioms of the Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory describe the properties we expect sets to have, in a mathematical way. The incredible part is that our language only contains one binary relation symbol, $in$, which is the membership symbol. Now remember that set theory only talks about sets, so all our objects are sets, including their members. This means that the most primitive notion is the question "Is this set a member of that set?.



This may sound baffling but we can encode numbers by sets and define all the mathematics within this universe, all this with only the membership relation to work with. The axioms tell us that sets have the following properties:




  1. Two sets are equal if and only if they have the same members.

  2. If we have a set, then the collection of all of its subsets is another set.

  3. If we have a set of sets $I$, then we have a set $U$ which is the union of those sets, namely all the members of $I$ are subsets of $U$, and $U$ is the smallest possible set with this property.

  4. There exists a set which has no members.

  5. If we have a set $x$ and a property $varphi$, then the collection of all the members of $x$ with the property $varphi$ is a set.

  6. If we can describe a function whose domain is a set, then its image is a set.

  7. There exists an infinite set$^*$.

  8. In every set $x$ which is not empty, there is a member $y$ which does not have any members shared with $x$.


These may sound a bit strange, but they serve a function. They tell us that some sets exist (empty set, infinite sets); they tell us how to create new sets from old sets; they tell us when two sets are equal; and they give us some strange condition on the membership relation (the last axiom).



It should be pointed that axioms 5 and 6 are not really axioms. They are schemata of axioms. This means that those are actually infinite lists of axioms which are easily described formally, and a computer can easily verify whether or not a certain sentence is an axiom from these lists or not.



Amongst the contradictions which these axioms solve is the one given by Russell, which is described by the collection of "all sets which are not members of themselves", this collection cannot be a set -- although we can describe this collection. With our axioms we have that if this collection is a set then we have a contradiction, so this is not a set to begin with.



But the axioms are important, because they give us a rigid framework for sets. Otherwise we just think of sets naively and so every collection we can describe must be a set, but Russell's collection cannot be a set. And that is the contradiction.





$^*$ I slightly dumb down this axiom, we require slightly more than just an infinite set, but it is easier to understand it this way. What we do require is that there is a set which "looks" like the collection of the natural numbers.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • Half of these axioms will be a bit much for high school students. A simple introduction might cover only axioms 1, 2, 4 and 5.
    – Dan Christensen
    May 7 '15 at 5:05










  • On axiom 5, may I suggest that the selection criterion $varphi$ not refer to the name of the subset being selected. Weird things can happen otherwise, e.g. every set would be an empty set.
    – Dan Christensen
    May 7 '15 at 5:26










  • @Dan, if you only cover part of these axioms, you will not be presenting ZFC. I don't know what you mean in your second comment.
    – Asaf Karagila
    May 7 '15 at 5:37










  • In my experience, I doubt that even the brightest high school students will understand the other axioms. You don't want to risk turning them off set theory for the rest of their lives. As for the second comment see "$B$ is not free in $varphi$" at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Axiom_schema_of_specification#Statement In an early beta version of my program, I left out this restriction by mistake and was able to prove that every set is an empty set!
    – Dan Christensen
    May 7 '15 at 5:50








  • 2




    @Dan: I get it. You have a blog. You have a proof assistant. Kudos. Again, I am trying to be informal. If you start talking about formulas, you need to explain they are first order formulas, you need to get into the logic. I chose not to do that. You're welcome to your opinion, but keep it to yourself. I have nothing more to add to this discussion.
    – Asaf Karagila
    May 7 '15 at 6:10



















0














By 'poking around' on wikipedia and elsewhere (like here, math.stackexchange), a person with mathematical talent will be able to get a 'layman's appreciation' of how Zermelo–Fraenkel (formal) set theory overcomes issues in naive set theory.



While perusing this topic (also as a 'layman'), I found the following passage from wikipedia,



$quad$Article: Axiom of regularity
$quad$Section: Regularity, the cumulative hierarchy, and types



of interest, especially since it's all in English.




Dana Scott (1974) went further and claimed that:



The truth is that there is only one satisfactory way of avoiding the
paradoxes: namely, the use of some form of the theory of types. That
was at the basis of both Russell's and Zermelo's intuitions. Indeed
the best way to regard Zermelo's theory is as a simplification and
extension of Russell's. (We mean Russell's simple theory of types, of
course.) The simplification was to make the types cumulative. Thus
mixing of types is easier and annoying repetitions are avoided. Once
the later types are allowed to accumulate the earlier ones, we can
then easily imagine extending the types into the transfinite—just how
far we want to go must necessarily be left open. Now Russell made his
types explicit in his notation and Zermelo left them implicit.
[emphasis in original]







share|cite|improve this answer























    Your Answer





    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    });
    });
    }, "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function() {
    var channelOptions = {
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    };
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
    createEditor();
    });
    }
    else {
    createEditor();
    }
    });

    function createEditor() {
    StackExchange.prepareEditor({
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader: {
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    },
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    });


    }
    });














    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function () {
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f309823%2fexplain-zermelo-fraenkel-set-theory-in-layman-terms%23new-answer', 'question_page');
    }
    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes








    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    19














    In mathematics we have an idea, some concept. For example the idea of "set" was modeled after the idea that two collections are equal if they have the same members.



    If I list your family it doesn't matter if I'm listing your father before you mother, or vice versa. I am only interested in the members. Similarly if I listed exactly the members of your family then this is a list of your family.



    So sets were models after this idea. But we want more from sets, we want them to have certain properties. And at first we assumed these properties must always hold, but it turned out that there is an inherent contradiction in naive set theory.



    So mathematicians of the early $20^{text{th}}$ century suggested axioms, which are strict rules that the mathematical objects called "sets" must obey. Amongst those mathematicians there were Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, after which the theory is named.



    Before we start, let me just add one definition. Given two sets, $A$ and $B$ we say that $A$ is a subset of $B$ if all the members of $A$ are members of $B$. For example, all the students in your class are also students in your high school, so the set of your classmates if a subset of the set of your schoolmates.



    The axioms of the Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory describe the properties we expect sets to have, in a mathematical way. The incredible part is that our language only contains one binary relation symbol, $in$, which is the membership symbol. Now remember that set theory only talks about sets, so all our objects are sets, including their members. This means that the most primitive notion is the question "Is this set a member of that set?.



    This may sound baffling but we can encode numbers by sets and define all the mathematics within this universe, all this with only the membership relation to work with. The axioms tell us that sets have the following properties:




    1. Two sets are equal if and only if they have the same members.

    2. If we have a set, then the collection of all of its subsets is another set.

    3. If we have a set of sets $I$, then we have a set $U$ which is the union of those sets, namely all the members of $I$ are subsets of $U$, and $U$ is the smallest possible set with this property.

    4. There exists a set which has no members.

    5. If we have a set $x$ and a property $varphi$, then the collection of all the members of $x$ with the property $varphi$ is a set.

    6. If we can describe a function whose domain is a set, then its image is a set.

    7. There exists an infinite set$^*$.

    8. In every set $x$ which is not empty, there is a member $y$ which does not have any members shared with $x$.


    These may sound a bit strange, but they serve a function. They tell us that some sets exist (empty set, infinite sets); they tell us how to create new sets from old sets; they tell us when two sets are equal; and they give us some strange condition on the membership relation (the last axiom).



    It should be pointed that axioms 5 and 6 are not really axioms. They are schemata of axioms. This means that those are actually infinite lists of axioms which are easily described formally, and a computer can easily verify whether or not a certain sentence is an axiom from these lists or not.



    Amongst the contradictions which these axioms solve is the one given by Russell, which is described by the collection of "all sets which are not members of themselves", this collection cannot be a set -- although we can describe this collection. With our axioms we have that if this collection is a set then we have a contradiction, so this is not a set to begin with.



    But the axioms are important, because they give us a rigid framework for sets. Otherwise we just think of sets naively and so every collection we can describe must be a set, but Russell's collection cannot be a set. And that is the contradiction.





    $^*$ I slightly dumb down this axiom, we require slightly more than just an infinite set, but it is easier to understand it this way. What we do require is that there is a set which "looks" like the collection of the natural numbers.






    share|cite|improve this answer























    • Half of these axioms will be a bit much for high school students. A simple introduction might cover only axioms 1, 2, 4 and 5.
      – Dan Christensen
      May 7 '15 at 5:05










    • On axiom 5, may I suggest that the selection criterion $varphi$ not refer to the name of the subset being selected. Weird things can happen otherwise, e.g. every set would be an empty set.
      – Dan Christensen
      May 7 '15 at 5:26










    • @Dan, if you only cover part of these axioms, you will not be presenting ZFC. I don't know what you mean in your second comment.
      – Asaf Karagila
      May 7 '15 at 5:37










    • In my experience, I doubt that even the brightest high school students will understand the other axioms. You don't want to risk turning them off set theory for the rest of their lives. As for the second comment see "$B$ is not free in $varphi$" at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Axiom_schema_of_specification#Statement In an early beta version of my program, I left out this restriction by mistake and was able to prove that every set is an empty set!
      – Dan Christensen
      May 7 '15 at 5:50








    • 2




      @Dan: I get it. You have a blog. You have a proof assistant. Kudos. Again, I am trying to be informal. If you start talking about formulas, you need to explain they are first order formulas, you need to get into the logic. I chose not to do that. You're welcome to your opinion, but keep it to yourself. I have nothing more to add to this discussion.
      – Asaf Karagila
      May 7 '15 at 6:10
















    19














    In mathematics we have an idea, some concept. For example the idea of "set" was modeled after the idea that two collections are equal if they have the same members.



    If I list your family it doesn't matter if I'm listing your father before you mother, or vice versa. I am only interested in the members. Similarly if I listed exactly the members of your family then this is a list of your family.



    So sets were models after this idea. But we want more from sets, we want them to have certain properties. And at first we assumed these properties must always hold, but it turned out that there is an inherent contradiction in naive set theory.



    So mathematicians of the early $20^{text{th}}$ century suggested axioms, which are strict rules that the mathematical objects called "sets" must obey. Amongst those mathematicians there were Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, after which the theory is named.



    Before we start, let me just add one definition. Given two sets, $A$ and $B$ we say that $A$ is a subset of $B$ if all the members of $A$ are members of $B$. For example, all the students in your class are also students in your high school, so the set of your classmates if a subset of the set of your schoolmates.



    The axioms of the Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory describe the properties we expect sets to have, in a mathematical way. The incredible part is that our language only contains one binary relation symbol, $in$, which is the membership symbol. Now remember that set theory only talks about sets, so all our objects are sets, including their members. This means that the most primitive notion is the question "Is this set a member of that set?.



    This may sound baffling but we can encode numbers by sets and define all the mathematics within this universe, all this with only the membership relation to work with. The axioms tell us that sets have the following properties:




    1. Two sets are equal if and only if they have the same members.

    2. If we have a set, then the collection of all of its subsets is another set.

    3. If we have a set of sets $I$, then we have a set $U$ which is the union of those sets, namely all the members of $I$ are subsets of $U$, and $U$ is the smallest possible set with this property.

    4. There exists a set which has no members.

    5. If we have a set $x$ and a property $varphi$, then the collection of all the members of $x$ with the property $varphi$ is a set.

    6. If we can describe a function whose domain is a set, then its image is a set.

    7. There exists an infinite set$^*$.

    8. In every set $x$ which is not empty, there is a member $y$ which does not have any members shared with $x$.


    These may sound a bit strange, but they serve a function. They tell us that some sets exist (empty set, infinite sets); they tell us how to create new sets from old sets; they tell us when two sets are equal; and they give us some strange condition on the membership relation (the last axiom).



    It should be pointed that axioms 5 and 6 are not really axioms. They are schemata of axioms. This means that those are actually infinite lists of axioms which are easily described formally, and a computer can easily verify whether or not a certain sentence is an axiom from these lists or not.



    Amongst the contradictions which these axioms solve is the one given by Russell, which is described by the collection of "all sets which are not members of themselves", this collection cannot be a set -- although we can describe this collection. With our axioms we have that if this collection is a set then we have a contradiction, so this is not a set to begin with.



    But the axioms are important, because they give us a rigid framework for sets. Otherwise we just think of sets naively and so every collection we can describe must be a set, but Russell's collection cannot be a set. And that is the contradiction.





    $^*$ I slightly dumb down this axiom, we require slightly more than just an infinite set, but it is easier to understand it this way. What we do require is that there is a set which "looks" like the collection of the natural numbers.






    share|cite|improve this answer























    • Half of these axioms will be a bit much for high school students. A simple introduction might cover only axioms 1, 2, 4 and 5.
      – Dan Christensen
      May 7 '15 at 5:05










    • On axiom 5, may I suggest that the selection criterion $varphi$ not refer to the name of the subset being selected. Weird things can happen otherwise, e.g. every set would be an empty set.
      – Dan Christensen
      May 7 '15 at 5:26










    • @Dan, if you only cover part of these axioms, you will not be presenting ZFC. I don't know what you mean in your second comment.
      – Asaf Karagila
      May 7 '15 at 5:37










    • In my experience, I doubt that even the brightest high school students will understand the other axioms. You don't want to risk turning them off set theory for the rest of their lives. As for the second comment see "$B$ is not free in $varphi$" at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Axiom_schema_of_specification#Statement In an early beta version of my program, I left out this restriction by mistake and was able to prove that every set is an empty set!
      – Dan Christensen
      May 7 '15 at 5:50








    • 2




      @Dan: I get it. You have a blog. You have a proof assistant. Kudos. Again, I am trying to be informal. If you start talking about formulas, you need to explain they are first order formulas, you need to get into the logic. I chose not to do that. You're welcome to your opinion, but keep it to yourself. I have nothing more to add to this discussion.
      – Asaf Karagila
      May 7 '15 at 6:10














    19












    19








    19






    In mathematics we have an idea, some concept. For example the idea of "set" was modeled after the idea that two collections are equal if they have the same members.



    If I list your family it doesn't matter if I'm listing your father before you mother, or vice versa. I am only interested in the members. Similarly if I listed exactly the members of your family then this is a list of your family.



    So sets were models after this idea. But we want more from sets, we want them to have certain properties. And at first we assumed these properties must always hold, but it turned out that there is an inherent contradiction in naive set theory.



    So mathematicians of the early $20^{text{th}}$ century suggested axioms, which are strict rules that the mathematical objects called "sets" must obey. Amongst those mathematicians there were Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, after which the theory is named.



    Before we start, let me just add one definition. Given two sets, $A$ and $B$ we say that $A$ is a subset of $B$ if all the members of $A$ are members of $B$. For example, all the students in your class are also students in your high school, so the set of your classmates if a subset of the set of your schoolmates.



    The axioms of the Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory describe the properties we expect sets to have, in a mathematical way. The incredible part is that our language only contains one binary relation symbol, $in$, which is the membership symbol. Now remember that set theory only talks about sets, so all our objects are sets, including their members. This means that the most primitive notion is the question "Is this set a member of that set?.



    This may sound baffling but we can encode numbers by sets and define all the mathematics within this universe, all this with only the membership relation to work with. The axioms tell us that sets have the following properties:




    1. Two sets are equal if and only if they have the same members.

    2. If we have a set, then the collection of all of its subsets is another set.

    3. If we have a set of sets $I$, then we have a set $U$ which is the union of those sets, namely all the members of $I$ are subsets of $U$, and $U$ is the smallest possible set with this property.

    4. There exists a set which has no members.

    5. If we have a set $x$ and a property $varphi$, then the collection of all the members of $x$ with the property $varphi$ is a set.

    6. If we can describe a function whose domain is a set, then its image is a set.

    7. There exists an infinite set$^*$.

    8. In every set $x$ which is not empty, there is a member $y$ which does not have any members shared with $x$.


    These may sound a bit strange, but they serve a function. They tell us that some sets exist (empty set, infinite sets); they tell us how to create new sets from old sets; they tell us when two sets are equal; and they give us some strange condition on the membership relation (the last axiom).



    It should be pointed that axioms 5 and 6 are not really axioms. They are schemata of axioms. This means that those are actually infinite lists of axioms which are easily described formally, and a computer can easily verify whether or not a certain sentence is an axiom from these lists or not.



    Amongst the contradictions which these axioms solve is the one given by Russell, which is described by the collection of "all sets which are not members of themselves", this collection cannot be a set -- although we can describe this collection. With our axioms we have that if this collection is a set then we have a contradiction, so this is not a set to begin with.



    But the axioms are important, because they give us a rigid framework for sets. Otherwise we just think of sets naively and so every collection we can describe must be a set, but Russell's collection cannot be a set. And that is the contradiction.





    $^*$ I slightly dumb down this axiom, we require slightly more than just an infinite set, but it is easier to understand it this way. What we do require is that there is a set which "looks" like the collection of the natural numbers.






    share|cite|improve this answer














    In mathematics we have an idea, some concept. For example the idea of "set" was modeled after the idea that two collections are equal if they have the same members.



    If I list your family it doesn't matter if I'm listing your father before you mother, or vice versa. I am only interested in the members. Similarly if I listed exactly the members of your family then this is a list of your family.



    So sets were models after this idea. But we want more from sets, we want them to have certain properties. And at first we assumed these properties must always hold, but it turned out that there is an inherent contradiction in naive set theory.



    So mathematicians of the early $20^{text{th}}$ century suggested axioms, which are strict rules that the mathematical objects called "sets" must obey. Amongst those mathematicians there were Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, after which the theory is named.



    Before we start, let me just add one definition. Given two sets, $A$ and $B$ we say that $A$ is a subset of $B$ if all the members of $A$ are members of $B$. For example, all the students in your class are also students in your high school, so the set of your classmates if a subset of the set of your schoolmates.



    The axioms of the Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory describe the properties we expect sets to have, in a mathematical way. The incredible part is that our language only contains one binary relation symbol, $in$, which is the membership symbol. Now remember that set theory only talks about sets, so all our objects are sets, including their members. This means that the most primitive notion is the question "Is this set a member of that set?.



    This may sound baffling but we can encode numbers by sets and define all the mathematics within this universe, all this with only the membership relation to work with. The axioms tell us that sets have the following properties:




    1. Two sets are equal if and only if they have the same members.

    2. If we have a set, then the collection of all of its subsets is another set.

    3. If we have a set of sets $I$, then we have a set $U$ which is the union of those sets, namely all the members of $I$ are subsets of $U$, and $U$ is the smallest possible set with this property.

    4. There exists a set which has no members.

    5. If we have a set $x$ and a property $varphi$, then the collection of all the members of $x$ with the property $varphi$ is a set.

    6. If we can describe a function whose domain is a set, then its image is a set.

    7. There exists an infinite set$^*$.

    8. In every set $x$ which is not empty, there is a member $y$ which does not have any members shared with $x$.


    These may sound a bit strange, but they serve a function. They tell us that some sets exist (empty set, infinite sets); they tell us how to create new sets from old sets; they tell us when two sets are equal; and they give us some strange condition on the membership relation (the last axiom).



    It should be pointed that axioms 5 and 6 are not really axioms. They are schemata of axioms. This means that those are actually infinite lists of axioms which are easily described formally, and a computer can easily verify whether or not a certain sentence is an axiom from these lists or not.



    Amongst the contradictions which these axioms solve is the one given by Russell, which is described by the collection of "all sets which are not members of themselves", this collection cannot be a set -- although we can describe this collection. With our axioms we have that if this collection is a set then we have a contradiction, so this is not a set to begin with.



    But the axioms are important, because they give us a rigid framework for sets. Otherwise we just think of sets naively and so every collection we can describe must be a set, but Russell's collection cannot be a set. And that is the contradiction.





    $^*$ I slightly dumb down this axiom, we require slightly more than just an infinite set, but it is easier to understand it this way. What we do require is that there is a set which "looks" like the collection of the natural numbers.







    share|cite|improve this answer














    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer








    edited Dec 26 '18 at 18:14









    John Bentin

    11.2k22453




    11.2k22453










    answered Feb 21 '13 at 4:04









    Asaf Karagila

    301k32425755




    301k32425755












    • Half of these axioms will be a bit much for high school students. A simple introduction might cover only axioms 1, 2, 4 and 5.
      – Dan Christensen
      May 7 '15 at 5:05










    • On axiom 5, may I suggest that the selection criterion $varphi$ not refer to the name of the subset being selected. Weird things can happen otherwise, e.g. every set would be an empty set.
      – Dan Christensen
      May 7 '15 at 5:26










    • @Dan, if you only cover part of these axioms, you will not be presenting ZFC. I don't know what you mean in your second comment.
      – Asaf Karagila
      May 7 '15 at 5:37










    • In my experience, I doubt that even the brightest high school students will understand the other axioms. You don't want to risk turning them off set theory for the rest of their lives. As for the second comment see "$B$ is not free in $varphi$" at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Axiom_schema_of_specification#Statement In an early beta version of my program, I left out this restriction by mistake and was able to prove that every set is an empty set!
      – Dan Christensen
      May 7 '15 at 5:50








    • 2




      @Dan: I get it. You have a blog. You have a proof assistant. Kudos. Again, I am trying to be informal. If you start talking about formulas, you need to explain they are first order formulas, you need to get into the logic. I chose not to do that. You're welcome to your opinion, but keep it to yourself. I have nothing more to add to this discussion.
      – Asaf Karagila
      May 7 '15 at 6:10


















    • Half of these axioms will be a bit much for high school students. A simple introduction might cover only axioms 1, 2, 4 and 5.
      – Dan Christensen
      May 7 '15 at 5:05










    • On axiom 5, may I suggest that the selection criterion $varphi$ not refer to the name of the subset being selected. Weird things can happen otherwise, e.g. every set would be an empty set.
      – Dan Christensen
      May 7 '15 at 5:26










    • @Dan, if you only cover part of these axioms, you will not be presenting ZFC. I don't know what you mean in your second comment.
      – Asaf Karagila
      May 7 '15 at 5:37










    • In my experience, I doubt that even the brightest high school students will understand the other axioms. You don't want to risk turning them off set theory for the rest of their lives. As for the second comment see "$B$ is not free in $varphi$" at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Axiom_schema_of_specification#Statement In an early beta version of my program, I left out this restriction by mistake and was able to prove that every set is an empty set!
      – Dan Christensen
      May 7 '15 at 5:50








    • 2




      @Dan: I get it. You have a blog. You have a proof assistant. Kudos. Again, I am trying to be informal. If you start talking about formulas, you need to explain they are first order formulas, you need to get into the logic. I chose not to do that. You're welcome to your opinion, but keep it to yourself. I have nothing more to add to this discussion.
      – Asaf Karagila
      May 7 '15 at 6:10
















    Half of these axioms will be a bit much for high school students. A simple introduction might cover only axioms 1, 2, 4 and 5.
    – Dan Christensen
    May 7 '15 at 5:05




    Half of these axioms will be a bit much for high school students. A simple introduction might cover only axioms 1, 2, 4 and 5.
    – Dan Christensen
    May 7 '15 at 5:05












    On axiom 5, may I suggest that the selection criterion $varphi$ not refer to the name of the subset being selected. Weird things can happen otherwise, e.g. every set would be an empty set.
    – Dan Christensen
    May 7 '15 at 5:26




    On axiom 5, may I suggest that the selection criterion $varphi$ not refer to the name of the subset being selected. Weird things can happen otherwise, e.g. every set would be an empty set.
    – Dan Christensen
    May 7 '15 at 5:26












    @Dan, if you only cover part of these axioms, you will not be presenting ZFC. I don't know what you mean in your second comment.
    – Asaf Karagila
    May 7 '15 at 5:37




    @Dan, if you only cover part of these axioms, you will not be presenting ZFC. I don't know what you mean in your second comment.
    – Asaf Karagila
    May 7 '15 at 5:37












    In my experience, I doubt that even the brightest high school students will understand the other axioms. You don't want to risk turning them off set theory for the rest of their lives. As for the second comment see "$B$ is not free in $varphi$" at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Axiom_schema_of_specification#Statement In an early beta version of my program, I left out this restriction by mistake and was able to prove that every set is an empty set!
    – Dan Christensen
    May 7 '15 at 5:50






    In my experience, I doubt that even the brightest high school students will understand the other axioms. You don't want to risk turning them off set theory for the rest of their lives. As for the second comment see "$B$ is not free in $varphi$" at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Axiom_schema_of_specification#Statement In an early beta version of my program, I left out this restriction by mistake and was able to prove that every set is an empty set!
    – Dan Christensen
    May 7 '15 at 5:50






    2




    2




    @Dan: I get it. You have a blog. You have a proof assistant. Kudos. Again, I am trying to be informal. If you start talking about formulas, you need to explain they are first order formulas, you need to get into the logic. I chose not to do that. You're welcome to your opinion, but keep it to yourself. I have nothing more to add to this discussion.
    – Asaf Karagila
    May 7 '15 at 6:10




    @Dan: I get it. You have a blog. You have a proof assistant. Kudos. Again, I am trying to be informal. If you start talking about formulas, you need to explain they are first order formulas, you need to get into the logic. I chose not to do that. You're welcome to your opinion, but keep it to yourself. I have nothing more to add to this discussion.
    – Asaf Karagila
    May 7 '15 at 6:10











    0














    By 'poking around' on wikipedia and elsewhere (like here, math.stackexchange), a person with mathematical talent will be able to get a 'layman's appreciation' of how Zermelo–Fraenkel (formal) set theory overcomes issues in naive set theory.



    While perusing this topic (also as a 'layman'), I found the following passage from wikipedia,



    $quad$Article: Axiom of regularity
    $quad$Section: Regularity, the cumulative hierarchy, and types



    of interest, especially since it's all in English.




    Dana Scott (1974) went further and claimed that:



    The truth is that there is only one satisfactory way of avoiding the
    paradoxes: namely, the use of some form of the theory of types. That
    was at the basis of both Russell's and Zermelo's intuitions. Indeed
    the best way to regard Zermelo's theory is as a simplification and
    extension of Russell's. (We mean Russell's simple theory of types, of
    course.) The simplification was to make the types cumulative. Thus
    mixing of types is easier and annoying repetitions are avoided. Once
    the later types are allowed to accumulate the earlier ones, we can
    then easily imagine extending the types into the transfinite—just how
    far we want to go must necessarily be left open. Now Russell made his
    types explicit in his notation and Zermelo left them implicit.
    [emphasis in original]







    share|cite|improve this answer




























      0














      By 'poking around' on wikipedia and elsewhere (like here, math.stackexchange), a person with mathematical talent will be able to get a 'layman's appreciation' of how Zermelo–Fraenkel (formal) set theory overcomes issues in naive set theory.



      While perusing this topic (also as a 'layman'), I found the following passage from wikipedia,



      $quad$Article: Axiom of regularity
      $quad$Section: Regularity, the cumulative hierarchy, and types



      of interest, especially since it's all in English.




      Dana Scott (1974) went further and claimed that:



      The truth is that there is only one satisfactory way of avoiding the
      paradoxes: namely, the use of some form of the theory of types. That
      was at the basis of both Russell's and Zermelo's intuitions. Indeed
      the best way to regard Zermelo's theory is as a simplification and
      extension of Russell's. (We mean Russell's simple theory of types, of
      course.) The simplification was to make the types cumulative. Thus
      mixing of types is easier and annoying repetitions are avoided. Once
      the later types are allowed to accumulate the earlier ones, we can
      then easily imagine extending the types into the transfinite—just how
      far we want to go must necessarily be left open. Now Russell made his
      types explicit in his notation and Zermelo left them implicit.
      [emphasis in original]







      share|cite|improve this answer


























        0












        0








        0






        By 'poking around' on wikipedia and elsewhere (like here, math.stackexchange), a person with mathematical talent will be able to get a 'layman's appreciation' of how Zermelo–Fraenkel (formal) set theory overcomes issues in naive set theory.



        While perusing this topic (also as a 'layman'), I found the following passage from wikipedia,



        $quad$Article: Axiom of regularity
        $quad$Section: Regularity, the cumulative hierarchy, and types



        of interest, especially since it's all in English.




        Dana Scott (1974) went further and claimed that:



        The truth is that there is only one satisfactory way of avoiding the
        paradoxes: namely, the use of some form of the theory of types. That
        was at the basis of both Russell's and Zermelo's intuitions. Indeed
        the best way to regard Zermelo's theory is as a simplification and
        extension of Russell's. (We mean Russell's simple theory of types, of
        course.) The simplification was to make the types cumulative. Thus
        mixing of types is easier and annoying repetitions are avoided. Once
        the later types are allowed to accumulate the earlier ones, we can
        then easily imagine extending the types into the transfinite—just how
        far we want to go must necessarily be left open. Now Russell made his
        types explicit in his notation and Zermelo left them implicit.
        [emphasis in original]







        share|cite|improve this answer














        By 'poking around' on wikipedia and elsewhere (like here, math.stackexchange), a person with mathematical talent will be able to get a 'layman's appreciation' of how Zermelo–Fraenkel (formal) set theory overcomes issues in naive set theory.



        While perusing this topic (also as a 'layman'), I found the following passage from wikipedia,



        $quad$Article: Axiom of regularity
        $quad$Section: Regularity, the cumulative hierarchy, and types



        of interest, especially since it's all in English.




        Dana Scott (1974) went further and claimed that:



        The truth is that there is only one satisfactory way of avoiding the
        paradoxes: namely, the use of some form of the theory of types. That
        was at the basis of both Russell's and Zermelo's intuitions. Indeed
        the best way to regard Zermelo's theory is as a simplification and
        extension of Russell's. (We mean Russell's simple theory of types, of
        course.) The simplification was to make the types cumulative. Thus
        mixing of types is easier and annoying repetitions are avoided. Once
        the later types are allowed to accumulate the earlier ones, we can
        then easily imagine extending the types into the transfinite—just how
        far we want to go must necessarily be left open. Now Russell made his
        types explicit in his notation and Zermelo left them implicit.
        [emphasis in original]








        share|cite|improve this answer














        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer








        edited 2 days ago

























        answered 2 days ago









        CopyPasteIt

        4,0301627




        4,0301627






























            draft saved

            draft discarded




















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.





            Some of your past answers have not been well-received, and you're in danger of being blocked from answering.


            Please pay close attention to the following guidance:


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f309823%2fexplain-zermelo-fraenkel-set-theory-in-layman-terms%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            Human spaceflight

            Can not write log (Is /dev/pts mounted?) - openpty in Ubuntu-on-Windows?

            File:DeusFollowingSea.jpg