Why is wave-function collapse still being taught in quantum mechanics? [closed]












4












$begingroup$


I don't really understand why wave-function collapse is still being taught while we seem to have better interpretations of QM available nowadays.



During the early development of quantum mechanics the measurement problem was a heavily debated topic, resulting in a general acceptance of the so-called Copenhagen interpretation. The two main problems with it are




  • It is not clear what physically defines an observation.

  • There is a certain faster than light interaction, thought this does not include faster than light travel of information.


Furthermore, the idea that the universe is nondeterministic was not appealing to some, for example to Einstein.



Since 1957 we have the "Many-worlds" interpretation of QM which resolves both these problems, makes QM deterministic again and gives a (IMO) much more physical interpretation. The original name Hugh Everett gave to his theory is "Correlation Interpretation" which I find actually more clear. Perhaps "Observer Entanglement" would be even more natural in the current idiom.



This theory was first mostly ignored, and even now seems to still not get the attention it deserves. Why are teachers often still teaching wave-function collapse, with all its shortcomings, when they teach QM?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$



closed as primarily opinion-based by ZeroTheHero, Gert, Cosmas Zachos, Ján Lalinský, rob Feb 10 at 2:41


Many good questions generate some degree of opinion based on expert experience, but answers to this question will tend to be almost entirely based on opinions, rather than facts, references, or specific expertise. If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.














  • 7




    $begingroup$
    This question should be closed because it seeks a debate rather than an answer.
    $endgroup$
    – ZeroTheHero
    Feb 9 at 17:32










  • $begingroup$
    I'm voting to close this question as off-topic because it is a question on the current status of teaching and provides a controversial opinion that may induce debate.
    $endgroup$
    – Ján Lalinský
    Feb 9 at 19:50








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I've deleted some comments that were answering the question, and responses to them.
    $endgroup$
    – David Z
    Feb 9 at 22:54










  • $begingroup$
    I see how this question evokes debate, but it was meant as a genuine question seeking an answer from an expert, namely a teacher, and as such it seems less opinion-based than for example this question. The accepted answer I think explains well why a teacher may make such a choice.
    $endgroup$
    – Mathijs
    Feb 10 at 10:14
















4












$begingroup$


I don't really understand why wave-function collapse is still being taught while we seem to have better interpretations of QM available nowadays.



During the early development of quantum mechanics the measurement problem was a heavily debated topic, resulting in a general acceptance of the so-called Copenhagen interpretation. The two main problems with it are




  • It is not clear what physically defines an observation.

  • There is a certain faster than light interaction, thought this does not include faster than light travel of information.


Furthermore, the idea that the universe is nondeterministic was not appealing to some, for example to Einstein.



Since 1957 we have the "Many-worlds" interpretation of QM which resolves both these problems, makes QM deterministic again and gives a (IMO) much more physical interpretation. The original name Hugh Everett gave to his theory is "Correlation Interpretation" which I find actually more clear. Perhaps "Observer Entanglement" would be even more natural in the current idiom.



This theory was first mostly ignored, and even now seems to still not get the attention it deserves. Why are teachers often still teaching wave-function collapse, with all its shortcomings, when they teach QM?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$



closed as primarily opinion-based by ZeroTheHero, Gert, Cosmas Zachos, Ján Lalinský, rob Feb 10 at 2:41


Many good questions generate some degree of opinion based on expert experience, but answers to this question will tend to be almost entirely based on opinions, rather than facts, references, or specific expertise. If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.














  • 7




    $begingroup$
    This question should be closed because it seeks a debate rather than an answer.
    $endgroup$
    – ZeroTheHero
    Feb 9 at 17:32










  • $begingroup$
    I'm voting to close this question as off-topic because it is a question on the current status of teaching and provides a controversial opinion that may induce debate.
    $endgroup$
    – Ján Lalinský
    Feb 9 at 19:50








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I've deleted some comments that were answering the question, and responses to them.
    $endgroup$
    – David Z
    Feb 9 at 22:54










  • $begingroup$
    I see how this question evokes debate, but it was meant as a genuine question seeking an answer from an expert, namely a teacher, and as such it seems less opinion-based than for example this question. The accepted answer I think explains well why a teacher may make such a choice.
    $endgroup$
    – Mathijs
    Feb 10 at 10:14














4












4








4





$begingroup$


I don't really understand why wave-function collapse is still being taught while we seem to have better interpretations of QM available nowadays.



During the early development of quantum mechanics the measurement problem was a heavily debated topic, resulting in a general acceptance of the so-called Copenhagen interpretation. The two main problems with it are




  • It is not clear what physically defines an observation.

  • There is a certain faster than light interaction, thought this does not include faster than light travel of information.


Furthermore, the idea that the universe is nondeterministic was not appealing to some, for example to Einstein.



Since 1957 we have the "Many-worlds" interpretation of QM which resolves both these problems, makes QM deterministic again and gives a (IMO) much more physical interpretation. The original name Hugh Everett gave to his theory is "Correlation Interpretation" which I find actually more clear. Perhaps "Observer Entanglement" would be even more natural in the current idiom.



This theory was first mostly ignored, and even now seems to still not get the attention it deserves. Why are teachers often still teaching wave-function collapse, with all its shortcomings, when they teach QM?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




I don't really understand why wave-function collapse is still being taught while we seem to have better interpretations of QM available nowadays.



During the early development of quantum mechanics the measurement problem was a heavily debated topic, resulting in a general acceptance of the so-called Copenhagen interpretation. The two main problems with it are




  • It is not clear what physically defines an observation.

  • There is a certain faster than light interaction, thought this does not include faster than light travel of information.


Furthermore, the idea that the universe is nondeterministic was not appealing to some, for example to Einstein.



Since 1957 we have the "Many-worlds" interpretation of QM which resolves both these problems, makes QM deterministic again and gives a (IMO) much more physical interpretation. The original name Hugh Everett gave to his theory is "Correlation Interpretation" which I find actually more clear. Perhaps "Observer Entanglement" would be even more natural in the current idiom.



This theory was first mostly ignored, and even now seems to still not get the attention it deserves. Why are teachers often still teaching wave-function collapse, with all its shortcomings, when they teach QM?







quantum-mechanics quantum-interpretations measurement-problem wavefunction-collapse






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Feb 9 at 14:56









Qmechanic

107k121991238




107k121991238










asked Feb 9 at 14:02









MathijsMathijs

383




383




closed as primarily opinion-based by ZeroTheHero, Gert, Cosmas Zachos, Ján Lalinský, rob Feb 10 at 2:41


Many good questions generate some degree of opinion based on expert experience, but answers to this question will tend to be almost entirely based on opinions, rather than facts, references, or specific expertise. If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.









closed as primarily opinion-based by ZeroTheHero, Gert, Cosmas Zachos, Ján Lalinský, rob Feb 10 at 2:41


Many good questions generate some degree of opinion based on expert experience, but answers to this question will tend to be almost entirely based on opinions, rather than facts, references, or specific expertise. If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.










  • 7




    $begingroup$
    This question should be closed because it seeks a debate rather than an answer.
    $endgroup$
    – ZeroTheHero
    Feb 9 at 17:32










  • $begingroup$
    I'm voting to close this question as off-topic because it is a question on the current status of teaching and provides a controversial opinion that may induce debate.
    $endgroup$
    – Ján Lalinský
    Feb 9 at 19:50








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I've deleted some comments that were answering the question, and responses to them.
    $endgroup$
    – David Z
    Feb 9 at 22:54










  • $begingroup$
    I see how this question evokes debate, but it was meant as a genuine question seeking an answer from an expert, namely a teacher, and as such it seems less opinion-based than for example this question. The accepted answer I think explains well why a teacher may make such a choice.
    $endgroup$
    – Mathijs
    Feb 10 at 10:14














  • 7




    $begingroup$
    This question should be closed because it seeks a debate rather than an answer.
    $endgroup$
    – ZeroTheHero
    Feb 9 at 17:32










  • $begingroup$
    I'm voting to close this question as off-topic because it is a question on the current status of teaching and provides a controversial opinion that may induce debate.
    $endgroup$
    – Ján Lalinský
    Feb 9 at 19:50








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I've deleted some comments that were answering the question, and responses to them.
    $endgroup$
    – David Z
    Feb 9 at 22:54










  • $begingroup$
    I see how this question evokes debate, but it was meant as a genuine question seeking an answer from an expert, namely a teacher, and as such it seems less opinion-based than for example this question. The accepted answer I think explains well why a teacher may make such a choice.
    $endgroup$
    – Mathijs
    Feb 10 at 10:14








7




7




$begingroup$
This question should be closed because it seeks a debate rather than an answer.
$endgroup$
– ZeroTheHero
Feb 9 at 17:32




$begingroup$
This question should be closed because it seeks a debate rather than an answer.
$endgroup$
– ZeroTheHero
Feb 9 at 17:32












$begingroup$
I'm voting to close this question as off-topic because it is a question on the current status of teaching and provides a controversial opinion that may induce debate.
$endgroup$
– Ján Lalinský
Feb 9 at 19:50






$begingroup$
I'm voting to close this question as off-topic because it is a question on the current status of teaching and provides a controversial opinion that may induce debate.
$endgroup$
– Ján Lalinský
Feb 9 at 19:50






1




1




$begingroup$
I've deleted some comments that were answering the question, and responses to them.
$endgroup$
– David Z
Feb 9 at 22:54




$begingroup$
I've deleted some comments that were answering the question, and responses to them.
$endgroup$
– David Z
Feb 9 at 22:54












$begingroup$
I see how this question evokes debate, but it was meant as a genuine question seeking an answer from an expert, namely a teacher, and as such it seems less opinion-based than for example this question. The accepted answer I think explains well why a teacher may make such a choice.
$endgroup$
– Mathijs
Feb 10 at 10:14




$begingroup$
I see how this question evokes debate, but it was meant as a genuine question seeking an answer from an expert, namely a teacher, and as such it seems less opinion-based than for example this question. The accepted answer I think explains well why a teacher may make such a choice.
$endgroup$
– Mathijs
Feb 10 at 10:14










3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes


















15












$begingroup$


  1. There are many interpretations, and while there are good arguments in favor of one or another, they are currently not distinguished experimentally. Therefore it is often considered prudent to leave the question of which interpretation is best to the field of philosophy, and focus in a physics course on the falsifiable aspects of the theory. The field of quantum interpretations is too deep to do the subject justice in an ordinary quantum mechanics course.


  2. The "Copenhagen Interpretation" is not very well-defined, but given point #1, it has several advantages over the others. One is historical inertia, but more importantly is its minimalism and instrumentalism. In its "textbook version," it avoids taking a position on the philosophical aspects of the theory, and focuses on calculation. It is often associated with the "Shut up and calculate!" mantra. "Collapse" of the wavefunction is not taken too literally as a dynamical process, but merely as a calculational tool. Quantum textbooks/courses tend not to dwell on the philosophy of Bohr or Heisenberg, and rather leave interpretation open to student preference should they pursue it through other resources.


  3. The philosophical problems with the interpretation, such as describing the experimental apparatus or observer quantum mechanically, are currently not an issue for any practicing physicist.







share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$









  • 2




    $begingroup$
    The claim "avoids taking a position on the philosophical aspects of the theory, and focuses on calculation" seems counterfactual. The Copenhagen interpretation is heavy on (misleading) ontological content, namely that some sort of "collapse" takes place and that "observers" are magically special.
    $endgroup$
    – R..
    Feb 10 at 1:14






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    @R.. To some extent, there's two CIs. There's a philosophical one, which gets into deep epistemological questions like "what is an observer?" Then there's the practical "it's quantum/[black box]/now it's classical -- pay no attention to the man behind the curtain". It's mostly this latter "shut up an calculate" one which is being taught. And it's used precisely because it avoids philosophy. Other interpretations like the MWI take a philosophical stand, without strong experimental backing. But when you ignore the transition, "QM [black box] classical" is experimentally validated.
    $endgroup$
    – R.M.
    Feb 10 at 2:08










  • $begingroup$
    "The philosophical problems with the interpretation, such as describing the experimental apparatus or observer quantum mechanically, are currently not an issue for any practicing physicist." I am not sure about that. The relatively recent article Physics Reports 525 (1), 1-166 (arxiv.org/abs/1107.2138) has over 100 citations.
    $endgroup$
    – akhmeteli
    Feb 10 at 17:40










  • $begingroup$
    I'd argue that Many-worlds is more minimalistic than copenhagen since it doesn't introduce the new concepts of observation or wavefunction collapse.
    $endgroup$
    – aquirdturtle
    Feb 16 at 1:26










  • $begingroup$
    @aquirdturtle I have my own views on interpretations that are sympathetic to Many-worlds, but I didn't consider elaborating on that to be within the scope of the question.
    $endgroup$
    – user1247
    Feb 16 at 1:32



















11












$begingroup$

So we are taught collapse at school, although there is no experimental evidence of collapse. You don't think this is good.



You suggest that we are taught many-worlds instead, although there is no experimental evidence of many worlds. Why is it better?



I would say there is no generally accepted interpretation of quantum theory (the mere existence of numerous interpretations seems to be an evidence of that). So which interpretation should be taught at school? I don't know. But do we need to change an unsatisfactory interpretation by another unsatisfactory interpretation?



You may believe that many-worlds is a satisfactory interpretation. According to some surveys, the majority of physicists do not favor many-worlds. So it is not obvious that students should be taught many-worlds. Should they be taught collapse? I don't think so, not without caveats.



A short answer to your question would be "because education has a lot of inertia", and it is not obvious that this is a bad thing.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$









  • 3




    $begingroup$
    There is no evidence for the truth or falsity of any interpretation of QM. That's why they are called "interpretations". If there was any evidence that one was true and the others were false, it would cease to be an "interpretation".
    $endgroup$
    – alephzero
    Feb 9 at 14:59






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @alephzero : I am not sure this is relevant to my answer. I criticized Copenhagen and many-worlds for some deadwood that has no experimental evidence. If you don't agree that such deadwood makes an interpretation less attractive/plausible, I have no problems with that.
    $endgroup$
    – akhmeteli
    Feb 9 at 15:42






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    It's not "lack of evidence", which implies falsifiability. It's non-falsifiability. And non-falsifiable content has no place in science.
    $endgroup$
    – R..
    Feb 10 at 1:15






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @R..: I am afraid I don't understand what you want to say and I don't want to guess (actually, I don't even know if your comment is intended for me or for alephzero). If you criticize my answer or my comment, I have no problem with that, but in that case I would appreciate some clarification.
    $endgroup$
    – akhmeteli
    Feb 10 at 1:32






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @James : arxiv.org/pdf/1612.00676.pdf (p. 6), arxiv.org/pdf/1301.1069.pdf (p. 9)
    $endgroup$
    – akhmeteli
    Feb 10 at 17:19



















9












$begingroup$

When something is taught a certain way in textbooks, then two things need to happen for that to change:




  1. Leading professionals in the field have to agree that the new approach is better, and start using it nearly universally in their research papers.


  2. The new approach gradually filters down into graduate textbooks, then upper-division undergrad textbooks, freshman texts, and popular writing.



An example of this process is the replacement of relativistic mass with invariant mass, which is still ongoing after several decades.



In the case of MWI versus Copenhagen, step #1 hasn't happened yet and probably never will. In nearly all applications, the choice of one or the other makes zero difference, even aesthetically. MWI also comes in a variety of flavors; some people do talk about measurements and splitting of worlds, while others find those concepts wrong or unhelpful. My own view (which has evolved as I've learned more about the subject) is that MWI is aesthetically preferable, but that if we want to explain why measurement seems to work in the way it does, ultimately we should probably talk about things like decoherence, and then the way measurements seem to work emerges as an approximation. (And the approximation can be bad if the measuring device is mesoscopic.) Personally, I use the language of MWI in talking to my students about QM, but I don't think it's wrong to use Copenhagen. Most freshman texts don't even talk about these issues, e.g., collapse is never even mentioned.



I do find it objectionable when upper-division texts introduce Copenhagen as if it were the only way to look at things, and without explicitly naming it as the Copenhagen interpretation.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$




















    3 Answers
    3






    active

    oldest

    votes








    3 Answers
    3






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    15












    $begingroup$


    1. There are many interpretations, and while there are good arguments in favor of one or another, they are currently not distinguished experimentally. Therefore it is often considered prudent to leave the question of which interpretation is best to the field of philosophy, and focus in a physics course on the falsifiable aspects of the theory. The field of quantum interpretations is too deep to do the subject justice in an ordinary quantum mechanics course.


    2. The "Copenhagen Interpretation" is not very well-defined, but given point #1, it has several advantages over the others. One is historical inertia, but more importantly is its minimalism and instrumentalism. In its "textbook version," it avoids taking a position on the philosophical aspects of the theory, and focuses on calculation. It is often associated with the "Shut up and calculate!" mantra. "Collapse" of the wavefunction is not taken too literally as a dynamical process, but merely as a calculational tool. Quantum textbooks/courses tend not to dwell on the philosophy of Bohr or Heisenberg, and rather leave interpretation open to student preference should they pursue it through other resources.


    3. The philosophical problems with the interpretation, such as describing the experimental apparatus or observer quantum mechanically, are currently not an issue for any practicing physicist.







    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$









    • 2




      $begingroup$
      The claim "avoids taking a position on the philosophical aspects of the theory, and focuses on calculation" seems counterfactual. The Copenhagen interpretation is heavy on (misleading) ontological content, namely that some sort of "collapse" takes place and that "observers" are magically special.
      $endgroup$
      – R..
      Feb 10 at 1:14






    • 2




      $begingroup$
      @R.. To some extent, there's two CIs. There's a philosophical one, which gets into deep epistemological questions like "what is an observer?" Then there's the practical "it's quantum/[black box]/now it's classical -- pay no attention to the man behind the curtain". It's mostly this latter "shut up an calculate" one which is being taught. And it's used precisely because it avoids philosophy. Other interpretations like the MWI take a philosophical stand, without strong experimental backing. But when you ignore the transition, "QM [black box] classical" is experimentally validated.
      $endgroup$
      – R.M.
      Feb 10 at 2:08










    • $begingroup$
      "The philosophical problems with the interpretation, such as describing the experimental apparatus or observer quantum mechanically, are currently not an issue for any practicing physicist." I am not sure about that. The relatively recent article Physics Reports 525 (1), 1-166 (arxiv.org/abs/1107.2138) has over 100 citations.
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 10 at 17:40










    • $begingroup$
      I'd argue that Many-worlds is more minimalistic than copenhagen since it doesn't introduce the new concepts of observation or wavefunction collapse.
      $endgroup$
      – aquirdturtle
      Feb 16 at 1:26










    • $begingroup$
      @aquirdturtle I have my own views on interpretations that are sympathetic to Many-worlds, but I didn't consider elaborating on that to be within the scope of the question.
      $endgroup$
      – user1247
      Feb 16 at 1:32
















    15












    $begingroup$


    1. There are many interpretations, and while there are good arguments in favor of one or another, they are currently not distinguished experimentally. Therefore it is often considered prudent to leave the question of which interpretation is best to the field of philosophy, and focus in a physics course on the falsifiable aspects of the theory. The field of quantum interpretations is too deep to do the subject justice in an ordinary quantum mechanics course.


    2. The "Copenhagen Interpretation" is not very well-defined, but given point #1, it has several advantages over the others. One is historical inertia, but more importantly is its minimalism and instrumentalism. In its "textbook version," it avoids taking a position on the philosophical aspects of the theory, and focuses on calculation. It is often associated with the "Shut up and calculate!" mantra. "Collapse" of the wavefunction is not taken too literally as a dynamical process, but merely as a calculational tool. Quantum textbooks/courses tend not to dwell on the philosophy of Bohr or Heisenberg, and rather leave interpretation open to student preference should they pursue it through other resources.


    3. The philosophical problems with the interpretation, such as describing the experimental apparatus or observer quantum mechanically, are currently not an issue for any practicing physicist.







    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$









    • 2




      $begingroup$
      The claim "avoids taking a position on the philosophical aspects of the theory, and focuses on calculation" seems counterfactual. The Copenhagen interpretation is heavy on (misleading) ontological content, namely that some sort of "collapse" takes place and that "observers" are magically special.
      $endgroup$
      – R..
      Feb 10 at 1:14






    • 2




      $begingroup$
      @R.. To some extent, there's two CIs. There's a philosophical one, which gets into deep epistemological questions like "what is an observer?" Then there's the practical "it's quantum/[black box]/now it's classical -- pay no attention to the man behind the curtain". It's mostly this latter "shut up an calculate" one which is being taught. And it's used precisely because it avoids philosophy. Other interpretations like the MWI take a philosophical stand, without strong experimental backing. But when you ignore the transition, "QM [black box] classical" is experimentally validated.
      $endgroup$
      – R.M.
      Feb 10 at 2:08










    • $begingroup$
      "The philosophical problems with the interpretation, such as describing the experimental apparatus or observer quantum mechanically, are currently not an issue for any practicing physicist." I am not sure about that. The relatively recent article Physics Reports 525 (1), 1-166 (arxiv.org/abs/1107.2138) has over 100 citations.
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 10 at 17:40










    • $begingroup$
      I'd argue that Many-worlds is more minimalistic than copenhagen since it doesn't introduce the new concepts of observation or wavefunction collapse.
      $endgroup$
      – aquirdturtle
      Feb 16 at 1:26










    • $begingroup$
      @aquirdturtle I have my own views on interpretations that are sympathetic to Many-worlds, but I didn't consider elaborating on that to be within the scope of the question.
      $endgroup$
      – user1247
      Feb 16 at 1:32














    15












    15








    15





    $begingroup$


    1. There are many interpretations, and while there are good arguments in favor of one or another, they are currently not distinguished experimentally. Therefore it is often considered prudent to leave the question of which interpretation is best to the field of philosophy, and focus in a physics course on the falsifiable aspects of the theory. The field of quantum interpretations is too deep to do the subject justice in an ordinary quantum mechanics course.


    2. The "Copenhagen Interpretation" is not very well-defined, but given point #1, it has several advantages over the others. One is historical inertia, but more importantly is its minimalism and instrumentalism. In its "textbook version," it avoids taking a position on the philosophical aspects of the theory, and focuses on calculation. It is often associated with the "Shut up and calculate!" mantra. "Collapse" of the wavefunction is not taken too literally as a dynamical process, but merely as a calculational tool. Quantum textbooks/courses tend not to dwell on the philosophy of Bohr or Heisenberg, and rather leave interpretation open to student preference should they pursue it through other resources.


    3. The philosophical problems with the interpretation, such as describing the experimental apparatus or observer quantum mechanically, are currently not an issue for any practicing physicist.







    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$




    1. There are many interpretations, and while there are good arguments in favor of one or another, they are currently not distinguished experimentally. Therefore it is often considered prudent to leave the question of which interpretation is best to the field of philosophy, and focus in a physics course on the falsifiable aspects of the theory. The field of quantum interpretations is too deep to do the subject justice in an ordinary quantum mechanics course.


    2. The "Copenhagen Interpretation" is not very well-defined, but given point #1, it has several advantages over the others. One is historical inertia, but more importantly is its minimalism and instrumentalism. In its "textbook version," it avoids taking a position on the philosophical aspects of the theory, and focuses on calculation. It is often associated with the "Shut up and calculate!" mantra. "Collapse" of the wavefunction is not taken too literally as a dynamical process, but merely as a calculational tool. Quantum textbooks/courses tend not to dwell on the philosophy of Bohr or Heisenberg, and rather leave interpretation open to student preference should they pursue it through other resources.


    3. The philosophical problems with the interpretation, such as describing the experimental apparatus or observer quantum mechanically, are currently not an issue for any practicing physicist.








    share|cite|improve this answer














    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer








    edited Feb 9 at 20:22









    Emilio Pisanty

    86.5k23215434




    86.5k23215434










    answered Feb 9 at 15:50









    user1247user1247

    3,73922157




    3,73922157








    • 2




      $begingroup$
      The claim "avoids taking a position on the philosophical aspects of the theory, and focuses on calculation" seems counterfactual. The Copenhagen interpretation is heavy on (misleading) ontological content, namely that some sort of "collapse" takes place and that "observers" are magically special.
      $endgroup$
      – R..
      Feb 10 at 1:14






    • 2




      $begingroup$
      @R.. To some extent, there's two CIs. There's a philosophical one, which gets into deep epistemological questions like "what is an observer?" Then there's the practical "it's quantum/[black box]/now it's classical -- pay no attention to the man behind the curtain". It's mostly this latter "shut up an calculate" one which is being taught. And it's used precisely because it avoids philosophy. Other interpretations like the MWI take a philosophical stand, without strong experimental backing. But when you ignore the transition, "QM [black box] classical" is experimentally validated.
      $endgroup$
      – R.M.
      Feb 10 at 2:08










    • $begingroup$
      "The philosophical problems with the interpretation, such as describing the experimental apparatus or observer quantum mechanically, are currently not an issue for any practicing physicist." I am not sure about that. The relatively recent article Physics Reports 525 (1), 1-166 (arxiv.org/abs/1107.2138) has over 100 citations.
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 10 at 17:40










    • $begingroup$
      I'd argue that Many-worlds is more minimalistic than copenhagen since it doesn't introduce the new concepts of observation or wavefunction collapse.
      $endgroup$
      – aquirdturtle
      Feb 16 at 1:26










    • $begingroup$
      @aquirdturtle I have my own views on interpretations that are sympathetic to Many-worlds, but I didn't consider elaborating on that to be within the scope of the question.
      $endgroup$
      – user1247
      Feb 16 at 1:32














    • 2




      $begingroup$
      The claim "avoids taking a position on the philosophical aspects of the theory, and focuses on calculation" seems counterfactual. The Copenhagen interpretation is heavy on (misleading) ontological content, namely that some sort of "collapse" takes place and that "observers" are magically special.
      $endgroup$
      – R..
      Feb 10 at 1:14






    • 2




      $begingroup$
      @R.. To some extent, there's two CIs. There's a philosophical one, which gets into deep epistemological questions like "what is an observer?" Then there's the practical "it's quantum/[black box]/now it's classical -- pay no attention to the man behind the curtain". It's mostly this latter "shut up an calculate" one which is being taught. And it's used precisely because it avoids philosophy. Other interpretations like the MWI take a philosophical stand, without strong experimental backing. But when you ignore the transition, "QM [black box] classical" is experimentally validated.
      $endgroup$
      – R.M.
      Feb 10 at 2:08










    • $begingroup$
      "The philosophical problems with the interpretation, such as describing the experimental apparatus or observer quantum mechanically, are currently not an issue for any practicing physicist." I am not sure about that. The relatively recent article Physics Reports 525 (1), 1-166 (arxiv.org/abs/1107.2138) has over 100 citations.
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 10 at 17:40










    • $begingroup$
      I'd argue that Many-worlds is more minimalistic than copenhagen since it doesn't introduce the new concepts of observation or wavefunction collapse.
      $endgroup$
      – aquirdturtle
      Feb 16 at 1:26










    • $begingroup$
      @aquirdturtle I have my own views on interpretations that are sympathetic to Many-worlds, but I didn't consider elaborating on that to be within the scope of the question.
      $endgroup$
      – user1247
      Feb 16 at 1:32








    2




    2




    $begingroup$
    The claim "avoids taking a position on the philosophical aspects of the theory, and focuses on calculation" seems counterfactual. The Copenhagen interpretation is heavy on (misleading) ontological content, namely that some sort of "collapse" takes place and that "observers" are magically special.
    $endgroup$
    – R..
    Feb 10 at 1:14




    $begingroup$
    The claim "avoids taking a position on the philosophical aspects of the theory, and focuses on calculation" seems counterfactual. The Copenhagen interpretation is heavy on (misleading) ontological content, namely that some sort of "collapse" takes place and that "observers" are magically special.
    $endgroup$
    – R..
    Feb 10 at 1:14




    2




    2




    $begingroup$
    @R.. To some extent, there's two CIs. There's a philosophical one, which gets into deep epistemological questions like "what is an observer?" Then there's the practical "it's quantum/[black box]/now it's classical -- pay no attention to the man behind the curtain". It's mostly this latter "shut up an calculate" one which is being taught. And it's used precisely because it avoids philosophy. Other interpretations like the MWI take a philosophical stand, without strong experimental backing. But when you ignore the transition, "QM [black box] classical" is experimentally validated.
    $endgroup$
    – R.M.
    Feb 10 at 2:08




    $begingroup$
    @R.. To some extent, there's two CIs. There's a philosophical one, which gets into deep epistemological questions like "what is an observer?" Then there's the practical "it's quantum/[black box]/now it's classical -- pay no attention to the man behind the curtain". It's mostly this latter "shut up an calculate" one which is being taught. And it's used precisely because it avoids philosophy. Other interpretations like the MWI take a philosophical stand, without strong experimental backing. But when you ignore the transition, "QM [black box] classical" is experimentally validated.
    $endgroup$
    – R.M.
    Feb 10 at 2:08












    $begingroup$
    "The philosophical problems with the interpretation, such as describing the experimental apparatus or observer quantum mechanically, are currently not an issue for any practicing physicist." I am not sure about that. The relatively recent article Physics Reports 525 (1), 1-166 (arxiv.org/abs/1107.2138) has over 100 citations.
    $endgroup$
    – akhmeteli
    Feb 10 at 17:40




    $begingroup$
    "The philosophical problems with the interpretation, such as describing the experimental apparatus or observer quantum mechanically, are currently not an issue for any practicing physicist." I am not sure about that. The relatively recent article Physics Reports 525 (1), 1-166 (arxiv.org/abs/1107.2138) has over 100 citations.
    $endgroup$
    – akhmeteli
    Feb 10 at 17:40












    $begingroup$
    I'd argue that Many-worlds is more minimalistic than copenhagen since it doesn't introduce the new concepts of observation or wavefunction collapse.
    $endgroup$
    – aquirdturtle
    Feb 16 at 1:26




    $begingroup$
    I'd argue that Many-worlds is more minimalistic than copenhagen since it doesn't introduce the new concepts of observation or wavefunction collapse.
    $endgroup$
    – aquirdturtle
    Feb 16 at 1:26












    $begingroup$
    @aquirdturtle I have my own views on interpretations that are sympathetic to Many-worlds, but I didn't consider elaborating on that to be within the scope of the question.
    $endgroup$
    – user1247
    Feb 16 at 1:32




    $begingroup$
    @aquirdturtle I have my own views on interpretations that are sympathetic to Many-worlds, but I didn't consider elaborating on that to be within the scope of the question.
    $endgroup$
    – user1247
    Feb 16 at 1:32











    11












    $begingroup$

    So we are taught collapse at school, although there is no experimental evidence of collapse. You don't think this is good.



    You suggest that we are taught many-worlds instead, although there is no experimental evidence of many worlds. Why is it better?



    I would say there is no generally accepted interpretation of quantum theory (the mere existence of numerous interpretations seems to be an evidence of that). So which interpretation should be taught at school? I don't know. But do we need to change an unsatisfactory interpretation by another unsatisfactory interpretation?



    You may believe that many-worlds is a satisfactory interpretation. According to some surveys, the majority of physicists do not favor many-worlds. So it is not obvious that students should be taught many-worlds. Should they be taught collapse? I don't think so, not without caveats.



    A short answer to your question would be "because education has a lot of inertia", and it is not obvious that this is a bad thing.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$









    • 3




      $begingroup$
      There is no evidence for the truth or falsity of any interpretation of QM. That's why they are called "interpretations". If there was any evidence that one was true and the others were false, it would cease to be an "interpretation".
      $endgroup$
      – alephzero
      Feb 9 at 14:59






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @alephzero : I am not sure this is relevant to my answer. I criticized Copenhagen and many-worlds for some deadwood that has no experimental evidence. If you don't agree that such deadwood makes an interpretation less attractive/plausible, I have no problems with that.
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 9 at 15:42






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      It's not "lack of evidence", which implies falsifiability. It's non-falsifiability. And non-falsifiable content has no place in science.
      $endgroup$
      – R..
      Feb 10 at 1:15






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @R..: I am afraid I don't understand what you want to say and I don't want to guess (actually, I don't even know if your comment is intended for me or for alephzero). If you criticize my answer or my comment, I have no problem with that, but in that case I would appreciate some clarification.
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 10 at 1:32






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @James : arxiv.org/pdf/1612.00676.pdf (p. 6), arxiv.org/pdf/1301.1069.pdf (p. 9)
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 10 at 17:19
















    11












    $begingroup$

    So we are taught collapse at school, although there is no experimental evidence of collapse. You don't think this is good.



    You suggest that we are taught many-worlds instead, although there is no experimental evidence of many worlds. Why is it better?



    I would say there is no generally accepted interpretation of quantum theory (the mere existence of numerous interpretations seems to be an evidence of that). So which interpretation should be taught at school? I don't know. But do we need to change an unsatisfactory interpretation by another unsatisfactory interpretation?



    You may believe that many-worlds is a satisfactory interpretation. According to some surveys, the majority of physicists do not favor many-worlds. So it is not obvious that students should be taught many-worlds. Should they be taught collapse? I don't think so, not without caveats.



    A short answer to your question would be "because education has a lot of inertia", and it is not obvious that this is a bad thing.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$









    • 3




      $begingroup$
      There is no evidence for the truth or falsity of any interpretation of QM. That's why they are called "interpretations". If there was any evidence that one was true and the others were false, it would cease to be an "interpretation".
      $endgroup$
      – alephzero
      Feb 9 at 14:59






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @alephzero : I am not sure this is relevant to my answer. I criticized Copenhagen and many-worlds for some deadwood that has no experimental evidence. If you don't agree that such deadwood makes an interpretation less attractive/plausible, I have no problems with that.
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 9 at 15:42






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      It's not "lack of evidence", which implies falsifiability. It's non-falsifiability. And non-falsifiable content has no place in science.
      $endgroup$
      – R..
      Feb 10 at 1:15






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @R..: I am afraid I don't understand what you want to say and I don't want to guess (actually, I don't even know if your comment is intended for me or for alephzero). If you criticize my answer or my comment, I have no problem with that, but in that case I would appreciate some clarification.
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 10 at 1:32






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @James : arxiv.org/pdf/1612.00676.pdf (p. 6), arxiv.org/pdf/1301.1069.pdf (p. 9)
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 10 at 17:19














    11












    11








    11





    $begingroup$

    So we are taught collapse at school, although there is no experimental evidence of collapse. You don't think this is good.



    You suggest that we are taught many-worlds instead, although there is no experimental evidence of many worlds. Why is it better?



    I would say there is no generally accepted interpretation of quantum theory (the mere existence of numerous interpretations seems to be an evidence of that). So which interpretation should be taught at school? I don't know. But do we need to change an unsatisfactory interpretation by another unsatisfactory interpretation?



    You may believe that many-worlds is a satisfactory interpretation. According to some surveys, the majority of physicists do not favor many-worlds. So it is not obvious that students should be taught many-worlds. Should they be taught collapse? I don't think so, not without caveats.



    A short answer to your question would be "because education has a lot of inertia", and it is not obvious that this is a bad thing.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$



    So we are taught collapse at school, although there is no experimental evidence of collapse. You don't think this is good.



    You suggest that we are taught many-worlds instead, although there is no experimental evidence of many worlds. Why is it better?



    I would say there is no generally accepted interpretation of quantum theory (the mere existence of numerous interpretations seems to be an evidence of that). So which interpretation should be taught at school? I don't know. But do we need to change an unsatisfactory interpretation by another unsatisfactory interpretation?



    You may believe that many-worlds is a satisfactory interpretation. According to some surveys, the majority of physicists do not favor many-worlds. So it is not obvious that students should be taught many-worlds. Should they be taught collapse? I don't think so, not without caveats.



    A short answer to your question would be "because education has a lot of inertia", and it is not obvious that this is a bad thing.







    share|cite|improve this answer












    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer










    answered Feb 9 at 14:53









    akhmeteliakhmeteli

    18.5k21844




    18.5k21844








    • 3




      $begingroup$
      There is no evidence for the truth or falsity of any interpretation of QM. That's why they are called "interpretations". If there was any evidence that one was true and the others were false, it would cease to be an "interpretation".
      $endgroup$
      – alephzero
      Feb 9 at 14:59






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @alephzero : I am not sure this is relevant to my answer. I criticized Copenhagen and many-worlds for some deadwood that has no experimental evidence. If you don't agree that such deadwood makes an interpretation less attractive/plausible, I have no problems with that.
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 9 at 15:42






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      It's not "lack of evidence", which implies falsifiability. It's non-falsifiability. And non-falsifiable content has no place in science.
      $endgroup$
      – R..
      Feb 10 at 1:15






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @R..: I am afraid I don't understand what you want to say and I don't want to guess (actually, I don't even know if your comment is intended for me or for alephzero). If you criticize my answer or my comment, I have no problem with that, but in that case I would appreciate some clarification.
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 10 at 1:32






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @James : arxiv.org/pdf/1612.00676.pdf (p. 6), arxiv.org/pdf/1301.1069.pdf (p. 9)
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 10 at 17:19














    • 3




      $begingroup$
      There is no evidence for the truth or falsity of any interpretation of QM. That's why they are called "interpretations". If there was any evidence that one was true and the others were false, it would cease to be an "interpretation".
      $endgroup$
      – alephzero
      Feb 9 at 14:59






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @alephzero : I am not sure this is relevant to my answer. I criticized Copenhagen and many-worlds for some deadwood that has no experimental evidence. If you don't agree that such deadwood makes an interpretation less attractive/plausible, I have no problems with that.
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 9 at 15:42






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      It's not "lack of evidence", which implies falsifiability. It's non-falsifiability. And non-falsifiable content has no place in science.
      $endgroup$
      – R..
      Feb 10 at 1:15






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @R..: I am afraid I don't understand what you want to say and I don't want to guess (actually, I don't even know if your comment is intended for me or for alephzero). If you criticize my answer or my comment, I have no problem with that, but in that case I would appreciate some clarification.
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 10 at 1:32






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @James : arxiv.org/pdf/1612.00676.pdf (p. 6), arxiv.org/pdf/1301.1069.pdf (p. 9)
      $endgroup$
      – akhmeteli
      Feb 10 at 17:19








    3




    3




    $begingroup$
    There is no evidence for the truth or falsity of any interpretation of QM. That's why they are called "interpretations". If there was any evidence that one was true and the others were false, it would cease to be an "interpretation".
    $endgroup$
    – alephzero
    Feb 9 at 14:59




    $begingroup$
    There is no evidence for the truth or falsity of any interpretation of QM. That's why they are called "interpretations". If there was any evidence that one was true and the others were false, it would cease to be an "interpretation".
    $endgroup$
    – alephzero
    Feb 9 at 14:59




    1




    1




    $begingroup$
    @alephzero : I am not sure this is relevant to my answer. I criticized Copenhagen and many-worlds for some deadwood that has no experimental evidence. If you don't agree that such deadwood makes an interpretation less attractive/plausible, I have no problems with that.
    $endgroup$
    – akhmeteli
    Feb 9 at 15:42




    $begingroup$
    @alephzero : I am not sure this is relevant to my answer. I criticized Copenhagen and many-worlds for some deadwood that has no experimental evidence. If you don't agree that such deadwood makes an interpretation less attractive/plausible, I have no problems with that.
    $endgroup$
    – akhmeteli
    Feb 9 at 15:42




    1




    1




    $begingroup$
    It's not "lack of evidence", which implies falsifiability. It's non-falsifiability. And non-falsifiable content has no place in science.
    $endgroup$
    – R..
    Feb 10 at 1:15




    $begingroup$
    It's not "lack of evidence", which implies falsifiability. It's non-falsifiability. And non-falsifiable content has no place in science.
    $endgroup$
    – R..
    Feb 10 at 1:15




    1




    1




    $begingroup$
    @R..: I am afraid I don't understand what you want to say and I don't want to guess (actually, I don't even know if your comment is intended for me or for alephzero). If you criticize my answer or my comment, I have no problem with that, but in that case I would appreciate some clarification.
    $endgroup$
    – akhmeteli
    Feb 10 at 1:32




    $begingroup$
    @R..: I am afraid I don't understand what you want to say and I don't want to guess (actually, I don't even know if your comment is intended for me or for alephzero). If you criticize my answer or my comment, I have no problem with that, but in that case I would appreciate some clarification.
    $endgroup$
    – akhmeteli
    Feb 10 at 1:32




    1




    1




    $begingroup$
    @James : arxiv.org/pdf/1612.00676.pdf (p. 6), arxiv.org/pdf/1301.1069.pdf (p. 9)
    $endgroup$
    – akhmeteli
    Feb 10 at 17:19




    $begingroup$
    @James : arxiv.org/pdf/1612.00676.pdf (p. 6), arxiv.org/pdf/1301.1069.pdf (p. 9)
    $endgroup$
    – akhmeteli
    Feb 10 at 17:19











    9












    $begingroup$

    When something is taught a certain way in textbooks, then two things need to happen for that to change:




    1. Leading professionals in the field have to agree that the new approach is better, and start using it nearly universally in their research papers.


    2. The new approach gradually filters down into graduate textbooks, then upper-division undergrad textbooks, freshman texts, and popular writing.



    An example of this process is the replacement of relativistic mass with invariant mass, which is still ongoing after several decades.



    In the case of MWI versus Copenhagen, step #1 hasn't happened yet and probably never will. In nearly all applications, the choice of one or the other makes zero difference, even aesthetically. MWI also comes in a variety of flavors; some people do talk about measurements and splitting of worlds, while others find those concepts wrong or unhelpful. My own view (which has evolved as I've learned more about the subject) is that MWI is aesthetically preferable, but that if we want to explain why measurement seems to work in the way it does, ultimately we should probably talk about things like decoherence, and then the way measurements seem to work emerges as an approximation. (And the approximation can be bad if the measuring device is mesoscopic.) Personally, I use the language of MWI in talking to my students about QM, but I don't think it's wrong to use Copenhagen. Most freshman texts don't even talk about these issues, e.g., collapse is never even mentioned.



    I do find it objectionable when upper-division texts introduce Copenhagen as if it were the only way to look at things, and without explicitly naming it as the Copenhagen interpretation.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$


















      9












      $begingroup$

      When something is taught a certain way in textbooks, then two things need to happen for that to change:




      1. Leading professionals in the field have to agree that the new approach is better, and start using it nearly universally in their research papers.


      2. The new approach gradually filters down into graduate textbooks, then upper-division undergrad textbooks, freshman texts, and popular writing.



      An example of this process is the replacement of relativistic mass with invariant mass, which is still ongoing after several decades.



      In the case of MWI versus Copenhagen, step #1 hasn't happened yet and probably never will. In nearly all applications, the choice of one or the other makes zero difference, even aesthetically. MWI also comes in a variety of flavors; some people do talk about measurements and splitting of worlds, while others find those concepts wrong or unhelpful. My own view (which has evolved as I've learned more about the subject) is that MWI is aesthetically preferable, but that if we want to explain why measurement seems to work in the way it does, ultimately we should probably talk about things like decoherence, and then the way measurements seem to work emerges as an approximation. (And the approximation can be bad if the measuring device is mesoscopic.) Personally, I use the language of MWI in talking to my students about QM, but I don't think it's wrong to use Copenhagen. Most freshman texts don't even talk about these issues, e.g., collapse is never even mentioned.



      I do find it objectionable when upper-division texts introduce Copenhagen as if it were the only way to look at things, and without explicitly naming it as the Copenhagen interpretation.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$
















        9












        9








        9





        $begingroup$

        When something is taught a certain way in textbooks, then two things need to happen for that to change:




        1. Leading professionals in the field have to agree that the new approach is better, and start using it nearly universally in their research papers.


        2. The new approach gradually filters down into graduate textbooks, then upper-division undergrad textbooks, freshman texts, and popular writing.



        An example of this process is the replacement of relativistic mass with invariant mass, which is still ongoing after several decades.



        In the case of MWI versus Copenhagen, step #1 hasn't happened yet and probably never will. In nearly all applications, the choice of one or the other makes zero difference, even aesthetically. MWI also comes in a variety of flavors; some people do talk about measurements and splitting of worlds, while others find those concepts wrong or unhelpful. My own view (which has evolved as I've learned more about the subject) is that MWI is aesthetically preferable, but that if we want to explain why measurement seems to work in the way it does, ultimately we should probably talk about things like decoherence, and then the way measurements seem to work emerges as an approximation. (And the approximation can be bad if the measuring device is mesoscopic.) Personally, I use the language of MWI in talking to my students about QM, but I don't think it's wrong to use Copenhagen. Most freshman texts don't even talk about these issues, e.g., collapse is never even mentioned.



        I do find it objectionable when upper-division texts introduce Copenhagen as if it were the only way to look at things, and without explicitly naming it as the Copenhagen interpretation.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$



        When something is taught a certain way in textbooks, then two things need to happen for that to change:




        1. Leading professionals in the field have to agree that the new approach is better, and start using it nearly universally in their research papers.


        2. The new approach gradually filters down into graduate textbooks, then upper-division undergrad textbooks, freshman texts, and popular writing.



        An example of this process is the replacement of relativistic mass with invariant mass, which is still ongoing after several decades.



        In the case of MWI versus Copenhagen, step #1 hasn't happened yet and probably never will. In nearly all applications, the choice of one or the other makes zero difference, even aesthetically. MWI also comes in a variety of flavors; some people do talk about measurements and splitting of worlds, while others find those concepts wrong or unhelpful. My own view (which has evolved as I've learned more about the subject) is that MWI is aesthetically preferable, but that if we want to explain why measurement seems to work in the way it does, ultimately we should probably talk about things like decoherence, and then the way measurements seem to work emerges as an approximation. (And the approximation can be bad if the measuring device is mesoscopic.) Personally, I use the language of MWI in talking to my students about QM, but I don't think it's wrong to use Copenhagen. Most freshman texts don't even talk about these issues, e.g., collapse is never even mentioned.



        I do find it objectionable when upper-division texts introduce Copenhagen as if it were the only way to look at things, and without explicitly naming it as the Copenhagen interpretation.







        share|cite|improve this answer












        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer










        answered Feb 9 at 22:27









        Ben CrowellBen Crowell

        53.7k6165313




        53.7k6165313















            Popular posts from this blog

            Human spaceflight

            Can not write log (Is /dev/pts mounted?) - openpty in Ubuntu-on-Windows?

            File:DeusFollowingSea.jpg