The theory of dense linear orders without end-points is not $2^omega$-categorical
$begingroup$
It seems best to prove this by counter example. Both $mathbb{R}$ and $I := mathbb{R} backslash mathbb{Q}$ under the usual order $<$ are models of the theory of dense linear orders without end-points and I think they are not isomorphic (if I understand the definition correctly, that means there is no order preserving bijection between $mathbb{R}$ and $I$). I couldn't manage to prove this.
My thoughts so far: suppose there exists such an isomorphism $beta: mathbb{R} to I$, then no irrational elements can be mapped to $beta(mathbb{Q})$, which messes up the order maybe because $mathbb{Q}$ is dense in $mathbb{R}$?
order-theory model-theory
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
It seems best to prove this by counter example. Both $mathbb{R}$ and $I := mathbb{R} backslash mathbb{Q}$ under the usual order $<$ are models of the theory of dense linear orders without end-points and I think they are not isomorphic (if I understand the definition correctly, that means there is no order preserving bijection between $mathbb{R}$ and $I$). I couldn't manage to prove this.
My thoughts so far: suppose there exists such an isomorphism $beta: mathbb{R} to I$, then no irrational elements can be mapped to $beta(mathbb{Q})$, which messes up the order maybe because $mathbb{Q}$ is dense in $mathbb{R}$?
order-theory model-theory
$endgroup$
2
$begingroup$
Hint: Which of those two orders are Dedekind complete?
$endgroup$
– Alessandro Codenotti
Dec 30 '18 at 23:01
add a comment |
$begingroup$
It seems best to prove this by counter example. Both $mathbb{R}$ and $I := mathbb{R} backslash mathbb{Q}$ under the usual order $<$ are models of the theory of dense linear orders without end-points and I think they are not isomorphic (if I understand the definition correctly, that means there is no order preserving bijection between $mathbb{R}$ and $I$). I couldn't manage to prove this.
My thoughts so far: suppose there exists such an isomorphism $beta: mathbb{R} to I$, then no irrational elements can be mapped to $beta(mathbb{Q})$, which messes up the order maybe because $mathbb{Q}$ is dense in $mathbb{R}$?
order-theory model-theory
$endgroup$
It seems best to prove this by counter example. Both $mathbb{R}$ and $I := mathbb{R} backslash mathbb{Q}$ under the usual order $<$ are models of the theory of dense linear orders without end-points and I think they are not isomorphic (if I understand the definition correctly, that means there is no order preserving bijection between $mathbb{R}$ and $I$). I couldn't manage to prove this.
My thoughts so far: suppose there exists such an isomorphism $beta: mathbb{R} to I$, then no irrational elements can be mapped to $beta(mathbb{Q})$, which messes up the order maybe because $mathbb{Q}$ is dense in $mathbb{R}$?
order-theory model-theory
order-theory model-theory
asked Dec 30 '18 at 22:54
Pel de PindaPel de Pinda
802213
802213
2
$begingroup$
Hint: Which of those two orders are Dedekind complete?
$endgroup$
– Alessandro Codenotti
Dec 30 '18 at 23:01
add a comment |
2
$begingroup$
Hint: Which of those two orders are Dedekind complete?
$endgroup$
– Alessandro Codenotti
Dec 30 '18 at 23:01
2
2
$begingroup$
Hint: Which of those two orders are Dedekind complete?
$endgroup$
– Alessandro Codenotti
Dec 30 '18 at 23:01
$begingroup$
Hint: Which of those two orders are Dedekind complete?
$endgroup$
– Alessandro Codenotti
Dec 30 '18 at 23:01
add a comment |
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
In the irrationals, take a sequence decreasing to $0$, then look at where those points map in the reals. Those real points will be a bounded decreasing sequence, therefore they will have a real limit $x$. Where does $x$ map in the irrationals ... call it $y$. Then $y<0$, but then there are irrationals between $y$ and $0$ and that should give you a contradiction since $x$ was the limit of the decreasing real sequence.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
(I decided to put it as an answer in the end)
A different $I$ that I believe is easier to work with is $I=Bbb Q ∪[0,1]$, assume that there is isomorphism $φ:Ito Bbb R$, then $φ(1.5)<φ(2)$, because it is order preserving, but $[1.5,2]$ in $I$ is countable but $[φ(1.5),φ(2)]$ in $Bbb R$ is uncountable, which leads to contradiction.
Also, although it is not $2^omega$-categorical, all models of cardinality $kappa$ that satisfy those properties are elementary equivalent: let $cal M,N$ be 2 models of that theory of size $kappa$, then, by (downward) Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, there exists $cal M',N'$ elementary substructure of $cal M,N$ respectively of size $omega$. Because the theory is $omega$-categorical, $cal M',N'$ are isomorphic, which implies that they are elementary equivalent, so $cal Mequiv M'equiv N'equiv N$
$endgroup$
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3057263%2fthe-theory-of-dense-linear-orders-without-end-points-is-not-2-omega-categoric%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
In the irrationals, take a sequence decreasing to $0$, then look at where those points map in the reals. Those real points will be a bounded decreasing sequence, therefore they will have a real limit $x$. Where does $x$ map in the irrationals ... call it $y$. Then $y<0$, but then there are irrationals between $y$ and $0$ and that should give you a contradiction since $x$ was the limit of the decreasing real sequence.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In the irrationals, take a sequence decreasing to $0$, then look at where those points map in the reals. Those real points will be a bounded decreasing sequence, therefore they will have a real limit $x$. Where does $x$ map in the irrationals ... call it $y$. Then $y<0$, but then there are irrationals between $y$ and $0$ and that should give you a contradiction since $x$ was the limit of the decreasing real sequence.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In the irrationals, take a sequence decreasing to $0$, then look at where those points map in the reals. Those real points will be a bounded decreasing sequence, therefore they will have a real limit $x$. Where does $x$ map in the irrationals ... call it $y$. Then $y<0$, but then there are irrationals between $y$ and $0$ and that should give you a contradiction since $x$ was the limit of the decreasing real sequence.
$endgroup$
In the irrationals, take a sequence decreasing to $0$, then look at where those points map in the reals. Those real points will be a bounded decreasing sequence, therefore they will have a real limit $x$. Where does $x$ map in the irrationals ... call it $y$. Then $y<0$, but then there are irrationals between $y$ and $0$ and that should give you a contradiction since $x$ was the limit of the decreasing real sequence.
answered Dec 30 '18 at 23:06
NedNed
1,993910
1,993910
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
(I decided to put it as an answer in the end)
A different $I$ that I believe is easier to work with is $I=Bbb Q ∪[0,1]$, assume that there is isomorphism $φ:Ito Bbb R$, then $φ(1.5)<φ(2)$, because it is order preserving, but $[1.5,2]$ in $I$ is countable but $[φ(1.5),φ(2)]$ in $Bbb R$ is uncountable, which leads to contradiction.
Also, although it is not $2^omega$-categorical, all models of cardinality $kappa$ that satisfy those properties are elementary equivalent: let $cal M,N$ be 2 models of that theory of size $kappa$, then, by (downward) Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, there exists $cal M',N'$ elementary substructure of $cal M,N$ respectively of size $omega$. Because the theory is $omega$-categorical, $cal M',N'$ are isomorphic, which implies that they are elementary equivalent, so $cal Mequiv M'equiv N'equiv N$
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
(I decided to put it as an answer in the end)
A different $I$ that I believe is easier to work with is $I=Bbb Q ∪[0,1]$, assume that there is isomorphism $φ:Ito Bbb R$, then $φ(1.5)<φ(2)$, because it is order preserving, but $[1.5,2]$ in $I$ is countable but $[φ(1.5),φ(2)]$ in $Bbb R$ is uncountable, which leads to contradiction.
Also, although it is not $2^omega$-categorical, all models of cardinality $kappa$ that satisfy those properties are elementary equivalent: let $cal M,N$ be 2 models of that theory of size $kappa$, then, by (downward) Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, there exists $cal M',N'$ elementary substructure of $cal M,N$ respectively of size $omega$. Because the theory is $omega$-categorical, $cal M',N'$ are isomorphic, which implies that they are elementary equivalent, so $cal Mequiv M'equiv N'equiv N$
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
(I decided to put it as an answer in the end)
A different $I$ that I believe is easier to work with is $I=Bbb Q ∪[0,1]$, assume that there is isomorphism $φ:Ito Bbb R$, then $φ(1.5)<φ(2)$, because it is order preserving, but $[1.5,2]$ in $I$ is countable but $[φ(1.5),φ(2)]$ in $Bbb R$ is uncountable, which leads to contradiction.
Also, although it is not $2^omega$-categorical, all models of cardinality $kappa$ that satisfy those properties are elementary equivalent: let $cal M,N$ be 2 models of that theory of size $kappa$, then, by (downward) Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, there exists $cal M',N'$ elementary substructure of $cal M,N$ respectively of size $omega$. Because the theory is $omega$-categorical, $cal M',N'$ are isomorphic, which implies that they are elementary equivalent, so $cal Mequiv M'equiv N'equiv N$
$endgroup$
(I decided to put it as an answer in the end)
A different $I$ that I believe is easier to work with is $I=Bbb Q ∪[0,1]$, assume that there is isomorphism $φ:Ito Bbb R$, then $φ(1.5)<φ(2)$, because it is order preserving, but $[1.5,2]$ in $I$ is countable but $[φ(1.5),φ(2)]$ in $Bbb R$ is uncountable, which leads to contradiction.
Also, although it is not $2^omega$-categorical, all models of cardinality $kappa$ that satisfy those properties are elementary equivalent: let $cal M,N$ be 2 models of that theory of size $kappa$, then, by (downward) Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, there exists $cal M',N'$ elementary substructure of $cal M,N$ respectively of size $omega$. Because the theory is $omega$-categorical, $cal M',N'$ are isomorphic, which implies that they are elementary equivalent, so $cal Mequiv M'equiv N'equiv N$
answered Dec 31 '18 at 7:01
HoloHolo
5,60321030
5,60321030
add a comment |
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3057263%2fthe-theory-of-dense-linear-orders-without-end-points-is-not-2-omega-categoric%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
2
$begingroup$
Hint: Which of those two orders are Dedekind complete?
$endgroup$
– Alessandro Codenotti
Dec 30 '18 at 23:01