The theory of dense linear orders without end-points is not $2^omega$-categorical












2












$begingroup$


It seems best to prove this by counter example. Both $mathbb{R}$ and $I := mathbb{R} backslash mathbb{Q}$ under the usual order $<$ are models of the theory of dense linear orders without end-points and I think they are not isomorphic (if I understand the definition correctly, that means there is no order preserving bijection between $mathbb{R}$ and $I$). I couldn't manage to prove this.



My thoughts so far: suppose there exists such an isomorphism $beta: mathbb{R} to I$, then no irrational elements can be mapped to $beta(mathbb{Q})$, which messes up the order maybe because $mathbb{Q}$ is dense in $mathbb{R}$?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    Hint: Which of those two orders are Dedekind complete?
    $endgroup$
    – Alessandro Codenotti
    Dec 30 '18 at 23:01
















2












$begingroup$


It seems best to prove this by counter example. Both $mathbb{R}$ and $I := mathbb{R} backslash mathbb{Q}$ under the usual order $<$ are models of the theory of dense linear orders without end-points and I think they are not isomorphic (if I understand the definition correctly, that means there is no order preserving bijection between $mathbb{R}$ and $I$). I couldn't manage to prove this.



My thoughts so far: suppose there exists such an isomorphism $beta: mathbb{R} to I$, then no irrational elements can be mapped to $beta(mathbb{Q})$, which messes up the order maybe because $mathbb{Q}$ is dense in $mathbb{R}$?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    Hint: Which of those two orders are Dedekind complete?
    $endgroup$
    – Alessandro Codenotti
    Dec 30 '18 at 23:01














2












2








2





$begingroup$


It seems best to prove this by counter example. Both $mathbb{R}$ and $I := mathbb{R} backslash mathbb{Q}$ under the usual order $<$ are models of the theory of dense linear orders without end-points and I think they are not isomorphic (if I understand the definition correctly, that means there is no order preserving bijection between $mathbb{R}$ and $I$). I couldn't manage to prove this.



My thoughts so far: suppose there exists such an isomorphism $beta: mathbb{R} to I$, then no irrational elements can be mapped to $beta(mathbb{Q})$, which messes up the order maybe because $mathbb{Q}$ is dense in $mathbb{R}$?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$




It seems best to prove this by counter example. Both $mathbb{R}$ and $I := mathbb{R} backslash mathbb{Q}$ under the usual order $<$ are models of the theory of dense linear orders without end-points and I think they are not isomorphic (if I understand the definition correctly, that means there is no order preserving bijection between $mathbb{R}$ and $I$). I couldn't manage to prove this.



My thoughts so far: suppose there exists such an isomorphism $beta: mathbb{R} to I$, then no irrational elements can be mapped to $beta(mathbb{Q})$, which messes up the order maybe because $mathbb{Q}$ is dense in $mathbb{R}$?







order-theory model-theory






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked Dec 30 '18 at 22:54









Pel de PindaPel de Pinda

802213




802213








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    Hint: Which of those two orders are Dedekind complete?
    $endgroup$
    – Alessandro Codenotti
    Dec 30 '18 at 23:01














  • 2




    $begingroup$
    Hint: Which of those two orders are Dedekind complete?
    $endgroup$
    – Alessandro Codenotti
    Dec 30 '18 at 23:01








2




2




$begingroup$
Hint: Which of those two orders are Dedekind complete?
$endgroup$
– Alessandro Codenotti
Dec 30 '18 at 23:01




$begingroup$
Hint: Which of those two orders are Dedekind complete?
$endgroup$
– Alessandro Codenotti
Dec 30 '18 at 23:01










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes


















3












$begingroup$

In the irrationals, take a sequence decreasing to $0$, then look at where those points map in the reals. Those real points will be a bounded decreasing sequence, therefore they will have a real limit $x$. Where does $x$ map in the irrationals ... call it $y$. Then $y<0$, but then there are irrationals between $y$ and $0$ and that should give you a contradiction since $x$ was the limit of the decreasing real sequence.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$





















    2












    $begingroup$

    (I decided to put it as an answer in the end)



    A different $I$ that I believe is easier to work with is $I=Bbb Q ∪[0,1]$, assume that there is isomorphism $φ:Ito Bbb R$, then $φ(1.5)<φ(2)$, because it is order preserving, but $[1.5,2]$ in $I$ is countable but $[φ(1.5),φ(2)]$ in $Bbb R$ is uncountable, which leads to contradiction.





    Also, although it is not $2^omega$-categorical, all models of cardinality $kappa$ that satisfy those properties are elementary equivalent: let $cal M,N$ be 2 models of that theory of size $kappa$, then, by (downward) Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, there exists $cal M',N'$ elementary substructure of $cal M,N$ respectively of size $omega$. Because the theory is $omega$-categorical, $cal M',N'$ are isomorphic, which implies that they are elementary equivalent, so $cal Mequiv M'equiv N'equiv N$






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













      Your Answer





      StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
      return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
      StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
      StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
      });
      });
      }, "mathjax-editing");

      StackExchange.ready(function() {
      var channelOptions = {
      tags: "".split(" "),
      id: "69"
      };
      initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

      StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
      // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
      if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
      StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
      createEditor();
      });
      }
      else {
      createEditor();
      }
      });

      function createEditor() {
      StackExchange.prepareEditor({
      heartbeatType: 'answer',
      autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
      convertImagesToLinks: true,
      noModals: true,
      showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
      reputationToPostImages: 10,
      bindNavPrevention: true,
      postfix: "",
      imageUploader: {
      brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
      contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
      allowUrls: true
      },
      noCode: true, onDemand: true,
      discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
      ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
      });


      }
      });














      draft saved

      draft discarded


















      StackExchange.ready(
      function () {
      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3057263%2fthe-theory-of-dense-linear-orders-without-end-points-is-not-2-omega-categoric%23new-answer', 'question_page');
      }
      );

      Post as a guest















      Required, but never shown

























      2 Answers
      2






      active

      oldest

      votes








      2 Answers
      2






      active

      oldest

      votes









      active

      oldest

      votes






      active

      oldest

      votes









      3












      $begingroup$

      In the irrationals, take a sequence decreasing to $0$, then look at where those points map in the reals. Those real points will be a bounded decreasing sequence, therefore they will have a real limit $x$. Where does $x$ map in the irrationals ... call it $y$. Then $y<0$, but then there are irrationals between $y$ and $0$ and that should give you a contradiction since $x$ was the limit of the decreasing real sequence.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$


















        3












        $begingroup$

        In the irrationals, take a sequence decreasing to $0$, then look at where those points map in the reals. Those real points will be a bounded decreasing sequence, therefore they will have a real limit $x$. Where does $x$ map in the irrationals ... call it $y$. Then $y<0$, but then there are irrationals between $y$ and $0$ and that should give you a contradiction since $x$ was the limit of the decreasing real sequence.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$
















          3












          3








          3





          $begingroup$

          In the irrationals, take a sequence decreasing to $0$, then look at where those points map in the reals. Those real points will be a bounded decreasing sequence, therefore they will have a real limit $x$. Where does $x$ map in the irrationals ... call it $y$. Then $y<0$, but then there are irrationals between $y$ and $0$ and that should give you a contradiction since $x$ was the limit of the decreasing real sequence.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$



          In the irrationals, take a sequence decreasing to $0$, then look at where those points map in the reals. Those real points will be a bounded decreasing sequence, therefore they will have a real limit $x$. Where does $x$ map in the irrationals ... call it $y$. Then $y<0$, but then there are irrationals between $y$ and $0$ and that should give you a contradiction since $x$ was the limit of the decreasing real sequence.







          share|cite|improve this answer












          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer










          answered Dec 30 '18 at 23:06









          NedNed

          1,993910




          1,993910























              2












              $begingroup$

              (I decided to put it as an answer in the end)



              A different $I$ that I believe is easier to work with is $I=Bbb Q ∪[0,1]$, assume that there is isomorphism $φ:Ito Bbb R$, then $φ(1.5)<φ(2)$, because it is order preserving, but $[1.5,2]$ in $I$ is countable but $[φ(1.5),φ(2)]$ in $Bbb R$ is uncountable, which leads to contradiction.





              Also, although it is not $2^omega$-categorical, all models of cardinality $kappa$ that satisfy those properties are elementary equivalent: let $cal M,N$ be 2 models of that theory of size $kappa$, then, by (downward) Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, there exists $cal M',N'$ elementary substructure of $cal M,N$ respectively of size $omega$. Because the theory is $omega$-categorical, $cal M',N'$ are isomorphic, which implies that they are elementary equivalent, so $cal Mequiv M'equiv N'equiv N$






              share|cite|improve this answer









              $endgroup$


















                2












                $begingroup$

                (I decided to put it as an answer in the end)



                A different $I$ that I believe is easier to work with is $I=Bbb Q ∪[0,1]$, assume that there is isomorphism $φ:Ito Bbb R$, then $φ(1.5)<φ(2)$, because it is order preserving, but $[1.5,2]$ in $I$ is countable but $[φ(1.5),φ(2)]$ in $Bbb R$ is uncountable, which leads to contradiction.





                Also, although it is not $2^omega$-categorical, all models of cardinality $kappa$ that satisfy those properties are elementary equivalent: let $cal M,N$ be 2 models of that theory of size $kappa$, then, by (downward) Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, there exists $cal M',N'$ elementary substructure of $cal M,N$ respectively of size $omega$. Because the theory is $omega$-categorical, $cal M',N'$ are isomorphic, which implies that they are elementary equivalent, so $cal Mequiv M'equiv N'equiv N$






                share|cite|improve this answer









                $endgroup$
















                  2












                  2








                  2





                  $begingroup$

                  (I decided to put it as an answer in the end)



                  A different $I$ that I believe is easier to work with is $I=Bbb Q ∪[0,1]$, assume that there is isomorphism $φ:Ito Bbb R$, then $φ(1.5)<φ(2)$, because it is order preserving, but $[1.5,2]$ in $I$ is countable but $[φ(1.5),φ(2)]$ in $Bbb R$ is uncountable, which leads to contradiction.





                  Also, although it is not $2^omega$-categorical, all models of cardinality $kappa$ that satisfy those properties are elementary equivalent: let $cal M,N$ be 2 models of that theory of size $kappa$, then, by (downward) Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, there exists $cal M',N'$ elementary substructure of $cal M,N$ respectively of size $omega$. Because the theory is $omega$-categorical, $cal M',N'$ are isomorphic, which implies that they are elementary equivalent, so $cal Mequiv M'equiv N'equiv N$






                  share|cite|improve this answer









                  $endgroup$



                  (I decided to put it as an answer in the end)



                  A different $I$ that I believe is easier to work with is $I=Bbb Q ∪[0,1]$, assume that there is isomorphism $φ:Ito Bbb R$, then $φ(1.5)<φ(2)$, because it is order preserving, but $[1.5,2]$ in $I$ is countable but $[φ(1.5),φ(2)]$ in $Bbb R$ is uncountable, which leads to contradiction.





                  Also, although it is not $2^omega$-categorical, all models of cardinality $kappa$ that satisfy those properties are elementary equivalent: let $cal M,N$ be 2 models of that theory of size $kappa$, then, by (downward) Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, there exists $cal M',N'$ elementary substructure of $cal M,N$ respectively of size $omega$. Because the theory is $omega$-categorical, $cal M',N'$ are isomorphic, which implies that they are elementary equivalent, so $cal Mequiv M'equiv N'equiv N$







                  share|cite|improve this answer












                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer










                  answered Dec 31 '18 at 7:01









                  HoloHolo

                  5,60321030




                  5,60321030






























                      draft saved

                      draft discarded




















































                      Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


                      • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                      But avoid



                      • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                      • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                      Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                      To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                      draft saved


                      draft discarded














                      StackExchange.ready(
                      function () {
                      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3057263%2fthe-theory-of-dense-linear-orders-without-end-points-is-not-2-omega-categoric%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                      }
                      );

                      Post as a guest















                      Required, but never shown





















































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown

































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown







                      Popular posts from this blog

                      Human spaceflight

                      Can not write log (Is /dev/pts mounted?) - openpty in Ubuntu-on-Windows?

                      File:DeusFollowingSea.jpg